Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Augustin-Jean Fresnel Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
The idea that there was a Copenhagen way of thinking was christened as the "Kopenhagener Geist der Quantentheorie" by Werner Heisenberg in the introduction to his 1930 textbook The Physical Principles of Quantum Theory, based on his 1929 lectures in Chicago (given at the invitation of Arthur Holly Compton).
It is a sad fact that Einstein, who had found more than any other scientist on the quantum interaction of electrons and photons, was largely ignored or misunderstood at this Solvay, when he again clearly described nonlocality
At the 1927 Solvay conference on physics entitled "Electrons and Photons," Niels Bohr and Heisenberg consolidated their Copenhagen view as a "complete" picture of quantum physics, despite the fact that they could not, or would not, visualize or otherwise explain exactly what is going on in the microscopic world of "quantum reality."
From the earliest presentations of the ideas of the supposed "founders" of quantum mechanics, Albert Einstein had deep misgivings of the work going on in Copenhagen, although he never doubted the calculating power of their new mathematical methods. He described their work as incomplete because it is based on the statistical results of many experiments so only makes probabilistic predictions about individual experiments. Einstein hoped to visualize what is going on in an underlying "objective reality."
Bohr seemed to deny the existence of a fundamental "reality," but he clearly knew and said that the physical world is largely independent of human observations. In classical physics, the physical world is assumed to be completely independent of the act of observing the world. In quantum physics, Heisenberg said that the result of an experiment depends on the free choice of the experimenter as to what to measure. The quantum world of photons and electrons might look like waves or look like particles depending on what we look for, rather than what they "are" as "things in themselves."
The information interpretation of quantum mechanics says there is only one world, the quantum world. Averaging over large numbers of quantum events explains why large objects appear to be classical
Copenhageners were proud of their limited ability to know. Bohr said:
There is no quantum world. There is only an abstract quantum physical description. It is wrong to think that the task of physics is to find out how nature is. Physics concerns what we can say about nature.Bohr thus put severe epistemological limits on knowing the Kantian "things in themselves," just as Immanuel Kant had put limits on reason. The British empiricist philosophers John Locke and David Hume had put the "primary" objects beyond the reach of our "secondary" sensory perceptions. In this respect, Bohr shared the positivist views of many other empirical scientists, Ernst Mach for example. Twentieth-century analytic language philosophers thought that philosophy (and even physics) could not solve some basic problems, but only "dis-solve" them by showing them to be conceptual errors.
Neither Bohr nor Heisenberg thought that macroscopic objects actually are classical. They both saw them as composed of microscopic quantum objects.
On the other hand, Bohr and Heisenberg emphasized the importance of conventional classical-physics language as a tool for knowledge. Since language evolved to describe the familiar world of "classical" objects in space and time, they insisted that somewhere between the quantum world and the classical world there must come a point when our observations and measurements can be expressible in classical concepts. They argued that a measurement apparatus and a particular observation must be describable classically in order for it to be understood and become knowledge in the mind of the observer.
The exact location of that transition from the quantum to the classically describable world was arbitrary, said Heisenberg. He called it a "cut" (Schnitt). Heisenberg's and especially John von Neumann's and Eugene Wigner's insistence on a critical role for a "conscious observer" has led to a great deal of nonsense being associated with the Copenhagen Interpretation and in the philosophy of quantum physics. Heisenberg may only have been trying to explain how knowledge reaches the observer's mind. For von Neumann and Wigner, the mind was considered a causal factor in the behavior of the quantum system.
Today, a large number of panpsychists, some philosophers, and a small number of scientists, still believe that the mind of a conscious observer is needed to cause the so-called "collapse" of the wave function. A relatively large number of scientists opposing the Copenhagen Interpretation believe that there are never any "collapses" in a universal wave function.
In the mid 1950's, Heisenberg reacted to David Bohm's 1952 "pilot-wave" interpretation of quantum mechanics by calling his own work the "Copenhagen Interpretation" and the only correct interpretation of quantum mechanics. A significant fraction of working quantum physicists say they agree with Heisenberg, though few have ever looked carefully into the fundamental assumptions of the Copenhagen Interpretation.
This is because they pick out from the Copenhagen Interpretation just the parts they need to make quantum mechanical calculations. Most textbooks start the story of quantum mechanics with the picture provided by the work of Heisenberg, Bohr, Max Born, Pascual Jordan, Paul Dirac, and of course Erwin Schrödinger.
What Exactly Is in the Copenhagen Interpretation?
There are several major components to the Copenhagen Interpretation, which most historians and philosophers of science agree on:
Opposition to the Copenhagen Interpretation
Albert Einstein, Louis deBroglie, and especially Erwin Schrödinger insisted on a more "complete" picture, not merely what can be said, but what we can "see," a visualization (Anschaulichkeit) of the microscopic world. But de Broglie and Schrödinger's emphasis on the wave picture made it difficult to understand material particles and their "quantum jumps." Indeed, Schrödinger and more recent physicists like John Bell and the decoherence theorists H. D. Zeh and Wojciech Zurek deny the existence of particles and the collapse of the wave function, which is central to the Copenhagen Interpretation.
Perhaps the main claim of those today denying the Copenhagen Interpretation (and standard quantum mechanics) began with Schrödinger's (nd later Bell's) claim that "there are no quantum jumps." Decoherence theorists and others favoring Everett's Many-Worlds Interpretation reject Dirac's projection postulate, a cornerstone of quantum theory.
Heisenberg had initially insisted on his own "matrix mechanics" of particles and their discrete, discontinuous, indeterministic behavior, the "quantum postulate" of unpredictable events that undermine the classical physics of causality. But Bohr told Heisenberg that his matrix mechanics was too narrow a view of the problem. This disappointed Heisenberg and almost ruptured their relationship. But Heisenberg came to accept the criticism and he eventually endorsed all of Bohr's deep philosophical view of quantum reality as unvisualizable.
In his September Como Lecture, a month before the 1927 Solvay conference, Bohr introduced his theory of "complementarity" as a "complete" theory. It combines the contradictory notions of wave and particle. Since both are required, they complement (and "complete") one another.
Although Bohr is often credited with integrating the dualism of waves and particles, it was Einstein who predicted this would be necessary as early as 1909. But in doing so, Bohr obfuscated further what was already a mysterious picture. How could something possibly be both a discrete particle and a continuous wave? Did Bohr endorse the continuous deterministic wave-mechanical views of Schrödinger? Not exactly, but Bohr's accepting Schrödinger's wave mechanics as equal to and complementing his matrix mechanics was most upsetting to Heisenberg.
Bohr's Como Lecture astonished Heisenberg by actually deriving (instead of Heisenberg's heuristic microscope argument) the uncertainty principle from the space-time wave picture alone, with no reference to the acausal dynamics of Heisenberg's picture! After this, Heisenberg did the same derivation in his 1930 text and subsequently completely accepted complementarity. Heisenberg spent the next several years widely promoting Bohr's views to scientists and philosophers around the world, though he frequently lectured on his mistaken, but easily understood, argument that looking at particles disturbs them. His microscope is even today included in many elementary physics textbooks.
Bohr said these contradictory wave and particle pictures are "complementary" and that both are needed for a "complete" picture. He co-opted Einstein's claim to a more "complete" picture of an objective" reality, one that might restore simultaneous knowledge of position and momentum, for example. Classical physics has twice the number of independent variables (and twice the information) as quantum physics. In this sense, it does seem more "complete."
Many critics of Copenhagen thought that Bohr deliberately and provocatively embraced logically contradictory notions - of continuous deterministic waves and discrete indeterministic particles - perhaps as evidence of Kantian limits on reason and human knowledge. Kant called such contradictory truths "antinomies." The contradictions only strengthened Bohr's epistemological resolve and his insistence that physics required a subjective view unable to reach the objective nature of the "things in themselves." As Heisenberg described it in his explanation of the Copenhagen Interpretation,
This again emphasizes a subjective element in the description of atomic events, since the measuring device has been constructed by the observer, and we have to remember that what we observe is not nature in itself but nature exposed to our method of questioning. Our scientific work in physics consists in asking questions about nature in the language that we possess and trying to get an answer from experiment by the means that are at our disposal.
References
Copenhagen Interpretation on Wikipedia>
Copenhagen Interpretation on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy>
"Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Theory", in Physics and Philosophy, Werner Heisenberg, 1958, pp.44-58
"The Copenhagen Interpretation", American Journal of Physics, 40, p.1098, Henry Stapp, 1972
"The History of Quantum Theory", in Physics and Philosophy, Werner Heisenberg, 1958, pp.30-43
For Teachers
For Scholars
|