Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Christoph Lehner
Christoph Lehner is a philosopher of physics who has specialized in the history of quantum physics. He has been an adviser and organizer of a series of international conferences on the history of quantum physics.
His contribution to the 2014 Cambridge Companion to Einstein was on "Realism and Einstein's Critique of Quantum Mechanics." It was one of three articles focusing on Einstein's quantum physics. The others were Olivier Darrigol's "The Quantum Enigma" and Roger H. Stuewer's "The Experimental Challenge of Light Quanta."
Lehner's view of Einstein's realism is beyond the simple (though correct) idea that there is a real world of objects "out there" largely independent of human beings and especially physicists. It goes well beyond the logical empiricist view, derived from Immanuel Kant and Ernst Mach that it can logically (and phenomenologically) only consist of the "immediately given" sensations of experience, Kant's phenomenal world and Mach's economic summary of experiences.
And Einstein's "objective reality" takes us beyond the nonsense of many current quantum ideas, such as that nothing happens until a physicist make a measurement, at which point the universe splits, doubling its mass in extreme violation of the conservation laws that are the basis for Einstein's beliefs.
Einstein's Method
Lehner builds on philosopher of science Arthur Fine's view that Einstein is committed to a method, that Einstein's realism is not an epistemological claim about the relation between science and a mind-independent reality, but rather a "methodological" claim about science and its apparatus." Lehner calls this "methodological realism."
Einstein himself describes his method in his 1933 Herbert Spencer Lecture "On the Method of Theoretical Physics." Science is built on fundamental general "principles" rather than constructed on particular "facts." Einstein's principles are often invariances, like the constant speed of light in all inertial frames and the relativity principle that laws of physics are the same in all such frames, or the principle of covariance in his general relativity.
But well beyond his success in relativity, Einstein's principles include laws of symmetry and the conservation laws that derive from them. Where Niels Bohr spent many years challenging the conservation of energy when light interacts with matter, to preserve his idea that the light is a continuous wave and not Einstein's light quantum (our photon), Einstein based his predictions of how a photon would interact with an electron on the principle of conservation of momentum and energy, following his discovery that light particles have momentum.
Does the molecule receive an impulse when it absorbs or emits the energy ε? For example, let us look at emission from the point of view of classical electrodynamics. When a body emits the radiation ε it suffers a recoil (momentum) ε/c if the entire amount of radiation energy is emitted in the same direction. If, however, the emission is a spatially symmetric process, e.g., a spherical wave, no recoil at all occurs. This alternative also plays a role in the quantum theory of radiation. When a molecule absorbs or emits the energy ε in the form of radiation during the transition between quantum theoretically possible states, then this elementary process can be viewed either as a completely or partially directed one in space, or also as a symmetrical (nondirected) one. It turns out that we arrive at a theory that is free of contradictions, only if we interpret those elementary processes as completely directed processes.Einstein had in 1916 and 1917 shown that Bohr's continuous and spherically symmetric radiation could not explain the randomly directed emissions of his light quanta. Bohr finally gave in when it was realized that Arthur Holly Compton's discovery of the "Compton Effect" had confirmed Einstein's prediction and invalidated the Bohr-Kramers-Slater claims. Another of Einstein's basic principles is what he called "Boltzmann's principle" equating entropy with the logarithm of the number of possible arrangements of material particles in phase space, S = k lnW. Lehner quotes Einstein's response to Moritz Schlick's book on physical reality, What we now designate as "real" in physics is doubtlessly the "spatiotemporally arranged," not the "immediately given." The immediately given can be an illusion. The spatiotemporally arranged can be a sterile concept that doesn't contribute to the elucidation of the connections between the immediately given.Lehner says that Einstein is proposing a distinction between "a phenomenal reality as the epistemological basis of our knowledge and a physical reality of spatiotemporally arranged events, which is an intellectual construct." But as Einstein emphasizes, this "construct" is not built on empirical facts, but on "principles,"which are "free inventions of the human mind" that turn out to fit those facts in our experimental tests. And Einstein's concern that "events" (point coincidences) in space time are "sterile" is precisely correct. Physics must also explain the behavior of "information structures," in particular their information exchanges (or interactions), which rise to the level of information "communications" between living things, the proper basis for the science of biology. Information (e.g., one of Boltzmann's arrangements of molecules) is neither matter nor energy, though it needs matter for its embodiment and energy for its communication (or interaction). Lehner's focus on space-time events reflects the concern of mathematical physicists who specialize in general relativity that "physical reality" consists of tenseless four-dimensional structures that describe all "past" and "future" events existing objectively the same as "present" events. This is John McTaggart's concept of an "A-series" and "B-series" of time. In McTaggart's "B-series" all events have unchanging descriptions. It eliminates change, progress, and evolution. It was a "timeless" view, or as J. J. C. Smart called it, a "tenseless" view. It was influenced by the Einstein-Minkowski "block universe" in which events in the future are already out there in the four-dimensional space-time, McTaggart argued that the A series is a necessary component of any full theory of time, since change only occurs in the "A series." But he said that the "A-series" is self-contradictory and that our perception of time is, therefore, ultimately an incoherent illusion. A "tenseless" universe is the epitome of a deterministic universe, a view favored by most mathematical physicists and many philosophers of science.
Wave-particle duality
Lehner cites H. A. Lorentz's description of Einstein's tentative view, somewhat before Louis de Broglie's "matter waves"( which de Broglie credited to Einstein). In this view, light quanta are point particles whose motion is determined (statistically, of course) by a guiding wave or field (Führungsfeld). This had been Einstein's relation of wave to particle since at least 1909.
Lehner gives an extended discussion of Einstein's short extemporaneous presentation at the blackboard during the fifth Solvay conference. And several more pages are devoted to the fruitless debate with Bohr about the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paper and the "completeness" of quantum mechanics.
Lehner then discusses the new relevance of EPR in the light of John Bell's proposed experiments to test for the existence of (what Bell thought was) Einstein's idea of "additional variables", later called "hidden variables" by David Bohm. Bell's logic impressed many, including Lehner, but his physics is questionable.
Bell's work was presented as a theorem about measurable differences in the angular dependence of correlations between distant observers of spin or polarization components of entangled particles. He presented the theorem as a "inequalities" that would appear at certain angles. Young experimenters inspired by the charismatic Bell were very excited that their measurements might prove quantum physics wrong and (at least Bell's version of) Einstein's deterministic theory true. This was Bell's hope of course.
When the experiments confirmed quantum mechanics, Bell said sadly "Einstein's program fails." But it was only Bell's idea of Einstein's program that failed.
In the years since Bell derived his inequalities a large number of physicists work on the "foundations of physics," most hoping for a return to a determinist view, which they mistakenly think Einstein wanted. Einstein never doubted that indeterminism and a statistical interpretation would always be a part of quantum physics. His hopes were for a deeper unified field theory that would somehow underlie quantum physics.
Lehner quotes Einstein's worry that such a field theory might be impossible. He quotes Einstein:
"I consider it entirely possible that physics cannot be founded on the concept of a field, i.e:, on continuous constructs. Then, nothing will remain of my whole castle in the air, including the theory of gravitation, [but also the whole rest of contemporary physics."Normal | Teacher | Scholar |