Arthur Fine
(1937-)
Arthur Fine is a philosopher of science noted for his early readings of
Albert Einstein's unpublished papers which became available to him at Princeton as part of the
Collected Papers of Albert Einstein project, edited by
John Stachel,
Don Howard, and others.
Especially important was Fine's critical reading of the Einstein-
Schrödinger correspondence of 1926, which prefigures their exchanges nine years later about
nonlocality and
nonseparability, following Einstein's epoch-making
EPR paper in 1935.
Fine traces the Einstein's debates in the late 1920's about interpretations of the "new" quantum mechanics with Bohr, Heisenberg, Schrödinger, and
Max Born, among others. Fine shows that the standard attacks on Einstein as not understanding their ideas, that he is
senile, are completely inappropriate. In particular, their portrayal of Einstein as hoping to restore
determinism and objecting to Heisenberg's
uncertainty principle is misplaced.
Fine shows that Einstein had five objections to the new quantum mechanics, even before Heisenberg formulated his uncertainty principle in mid-1927.
(1) the equations of the theory are not relativistically invariant;
(2) it does not yield the classical behavior of macroscopic objects to a good approximation;
(3) it leads to correlations among spatially separated objects that appear to violate action-by-contact principles;
(4) it is an essentially statistical theory that seems incapable even of describing the behavior of individual systems;
and (5) the scope of the commutation relations may not in fact be so broad as the theory supposes.
(The Shaky Game, p.28)
Fine is correct that Einstein held these views in early 1927. But we have shown that he suspected many of them (especially 1, 3) as early as 1905. That
chance is involved he saw clearly in 1916, so
alternative possibilities exist with calculable
probabilities. Quantum mechanics is a
statistical theory that applies to
ensembles of
identical systems. It does not describe individual systems.
Sometime, likely before 1920, Einstein described the
Führungsfeld and the
Gespensterfeld to
Max Born and others. For Einstein, these wave fields are the probabilities of finding a light quantum. Born wrote in his 1926 paper on atomic collisions
I shall recall a remark
that Einstein made about the behavior of the wave field and light quanta. He said that
perhaps the waves only have to be wherever one needs to know the path of the
corpuscular light quanta, and in that sense, he spoke of a “ghost field.” It determines the
probability that a light quantum - viz., the carrier of energy and impulse – follows a
certain path; however, the field itself is ascribed no energy and no impulse
(Quantum mechanics of collision processes (Quantenmechanik der Stoßvorgänge), Zeitschrift für Physik, 38 (1926), 803-827)
Einstein made his probability view explicit in 1927 at the Solvay Conference where he said
|ψ|2 expresses the probability that there exists at the point considered a particular particle of the cloud, for example at a given point on the screen.
(Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference, G. Bacciagaluppi and A. Valentini, 2009. pp.440-442)
References
"
Einstein's Critique of Quantum Theory," Chapter 3 of
The Shaky Game
Normal |
Teacher |
Scholar