Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington David Shiang Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Harald Atmanspacher
Harald Atmanspacher is Head of the Department of Theory and Data Analysis of the Institute for Frontier Areas of Psychology and Mental Health, Freiburg, Faculty Member of the C. G. Jung Institute, Zurich, Associate Fellow at the Collegium Helveticum, Zurich, at the ETH, as well as at the University of Zurich. Since 2003 he is Editor-in-Chief of the journal Mind and Matter, published by the Society for Mind-Matter Research.
His main fields of work are nonlinear dynamics, complex systems, and psychophysical dualism. He is, with Hans Primas, an editor of Recasting Reality: Wolfgang Pauli's Philosophical Ideas and Contemporary Science and he wrote the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy page on
Quantum Approaches to Consciousness.
With Robert Bishop, Atmanspacher developed the theory of "contextual emergence," in which the description of properties of a lower level of emergence offers necessary but not sufficient conditions to rigorously describe the properties of the next higher level. The sufficient conditions are provided by "contextual" and contingent conditions.
Atmanspacher distinguishes between levels of description and levels of reality, i.e. between epistemological and ontological frameworks for reduction and emergence. He says:
Broadly speaking, descriptive terms are subjects of epistemological discourse while elements of reality are subjects of ontological discourse. Both types of discourse are used in reductionist and emergentist approaches. The concept of reference establishes a connection between descriptive terms and described elements of reality (leaving aside difficult questions about reference itself). If one wants to have the option of ontic elements at each level of description rather than only at one or a few fundamental levels, a straightforward and strictly reductive scheme for interlevel relations becomes impossible and must be relaxed. The way in which ontic and epistemic descriptions are related to each other motivates contextual emergence as a viable alternative. In order to clearly distinguish between different concepts of reduction and emergence, it is desirable to have a transparent classification scheme, so that the basic characteristics of these concepts can be discussed coherently. A useful approach toward such a classification is based on the role which contingent contexts play in reduction and emergence. More precisely, the way in which necessary and sufficient conditions are assumed in the relation between different levels of description can be used to distinguish four classes of relations:Atmanspacher situates contextual emergence in a matrix of related pictures of reductionism and emergence. He says the way in which necessary and sufficient conditions are assumed in the relation between different levels of description can be used to distinguish four classes of relations: (1) The description of features of a system at a particular level of description offers both necessary and sufficient conditions to rigorously derive the description of features at a higher level. This is the strictest possible form of reduction. It was most popular under the influence of positivist thinking in the mid-20th century. (2) The description of features of a system at a particular level of description offers necessary but not sufficient conditions to derive the description of features at a higher level. This version is called contextual emergence, because contingent contextual conditions are required in addition to the lower-level description for a rigorous derivation of higher-level features. (3) The description of features of a system at a particular level of description offers sufficient but not necessary conditions to derive the description of features at a higher level. This version includes the idea that a lower-level description offers multiple realizations of a particular feature at a higher level, which is characteristic of supervenience. (4) The description of features of a system at a particular level of description offers neither necessary nor sufficient conditions to derive the description of features at a higher level. This represents a form of radical emergence insofar as there are no relevant conditions connecting the two levels whatsoever.In a recent article, Atmanspacher makes the argument that genuine chance may be involved in sub-cellular brain processes, although neural networks may be adequately determined. Any distribution characterizing a state can in principle be interpreted as due to genuine chance (ontically) or due to ignorance (epistemically). This ignorance, or missing information, can in turn be deliberate, e.g. in order to disregard details that are inessential in a particular context, or it can be caused by uncontrollable perturbations. At the ion channel level, where quantum effects must be expected to occur, an ontic interpretation in terms of indeterminate states is possible or likely. However, the fact that the stochastic dynamics of ion channels typically yields highly reliable and precise neuronal behaviour suggests that any potentially genuine micro-stochasticity is inefficacious at the neuronal level (and even more so at the network level). Therefore, statistical neuronal states are assumed to be of epistemic nature and genuine indeterministic contributions to the dynamics of neurons seem to be of low relevance. After all, the representation of the neurodynamics in a neuronal state space amounts to a fairly well-defined trajectory of quasi-ontic states... Since stochastic descriptions can generally be transformed into deterministic descriptions, it is an important issue whether or not there is a genuinely stochastic neuronal dynamics for which a (hidden) deterministic interpretation can be excluded. To all our present knowledge this is the case for stochastic quantum processes, for which the Schrödinger dynamics breaks down so that they are to be conceived as ontologically indeterministic. Although the neurobiological literature does not refer to quantum phenomena a lot, it would be premature to assume that indeterministic quantum processes do not occur on relevant scales in the brain."Two-stage models of free will" combine ontologically indeterministic quantum processes as a low-level generator of noise in the brain with more macroscopic but still stochastic processes. They use quantum-level indeterminism in the first stage, which generates alternative possibilities for action. These are evaluated in the second stage, which is a "willful" and "adequately" determined process that considers motives, reasons, and desires to choose between the "freely" generated alternatives of the first stage. The two-stage model can be described simply as first chance, then choice (cf. the book Chance and Choice, ed. by Atmanspacher and Bishop), or first "free" then "will." As it was first described by William James, it is a model of "mental evolution" of creative new ideas analogous to the two-step process of Darwinian evolution of new species. Wolfgang Pauli and Carl Jung
Atmanspacher is a faculty member of the C.G. Jung-Institut, Zurich, and has researched the extraordinary twenty-year collaboration between physicist Wolfgang Pauli and psychologist Carl Jung, culminating in a study of their dual-aspect monism.
Dual-Aspect Monism
Atmanspacher explains the relationship of "dual-aspect" to "neutral" monism
The classic starting point for most contemporary discussions of mind-matter relations is Descartes' ontologically conceived dualism of the mental (res cogitans, thought) and the material (res extensa, extended matter). In the history of philosophy, Descartes' position was immediately upgraded, criticized, or replaced by essentially three forms of thought: (i) alternative dualistic approaches (occasionalism, parallelism), (ii) essentially monistic approaches (idealism, materialism), and (iii) approaches combining (i) and (ii) by assuming a monistic domain underlying the mind-matter distinction. An early protagonist of this latter view is Baruch de Spinoza. Spinoza's monism provides an elegant and robust sense in which mind and matter are related to a "unity of essence". It does so by concatenating an ontological monism with an epistemological dualism, yielding an overall worldview in which both philosophy and the sciences can find appropriate places and mutual relations. This framework began to be explicitly exploited in the mid 19th century, by both philosophers and scientists, and today we can recognize two main reactions to Spinozism, called dual-aspect monism and neutral monism. Unfortunately, there is no authoritative delineation of the two - the many versions of dual-aspect monism and neutral monism that are around today have a tendency to blend into each other in ways that make clear assignments to one or the other problematic. This can be seen in Stubenberg's (2010-SEP) excellent overview, see also Silberstein's (2009) taxonomy and Seager's (2009) discussion, among others. There are important commonalities but also key differences between dual-aspect monism and neutral monism:Atmanspacher connects dual-aspect monism with the important concept of complementarity, one of many great dualisms.1. For neutral monists both mind and matter reduce to an underlying, neutral domain, while for dual-aspect monists mind and matter are two basic and irreducible aspects of that underlying domain. In both frameworks, the underlying, ontic domain (and its elements, respectively), is mostly characterized as neither mental nor material. 2. For neutral monists mind and matter are separate insofar as particular configurations of elements of the neutral domain underlie the mental while other, distinct configurations of elements of the neutral domain underlie the material. For dual-aspect monists the underlying, ontic domain manifests itself generally and equally under both aspects, tied together inseparably.An interesting implication of these two criteria is that the aspects in dual-aspect monism are not a priori given, but depend on epistemic issues and contexts. Distinctions of aspects are generated by "epistemic splits" of the distinction-free, unseparated underlying domain, and in principle there can be as many aspects as there are contexts. This is at variance with neutral monism where the mind-matter distinction is assumed to be preformed in the neutral domain: particular configurations of neutral elements underlie the mental while other, distinct configurations of neutral elements underlie the material. Moreover, the two criteria entail an interesting further dividing line between prevalent philosophical inclinations toward the underlying domain. For dual-aspect monists this domain is apprehensible only indirectly, through the aspects, while neutral monists deny this restriction. Therefore, it is natural for dual-aspect monists to nurture metaphysical conceptions of the underlying domain, while neutral monists typically refer to direct, basic, pure, raw modes of apprehending it, for instance experientially or phenomenologically. Stubenberg's (2010) review clearly supports this observation. Ernst Mach, William James, and Bertrand Russell, the forefront of neutral monism, refer to "sensation", "pure experience", and again "sensation", respectively, concerning the neutral domain, and these notions are redigested by other neutral monists such as Avenarius, Petzoldt, Perry, Holt, Sayre etc. Their empirical, hence anti-metaphysical, inclination explains why their notions of the neutral domain all bear the risk of confusing the neutral with some mental capacity. Assuming that the neutral can be apprehended directly, how could it be apprehended if not mentally? By contrast, dual-aspect monists do not hesitate to embrace ontology and metaphysics. Since their underlying domain (substantial or processual) is conceived of metaphysically, it cannot be apprehensible in any direct way but manifests itself in its aspects. Beyond the well-known historical representatives of dual-aspect monism such as Spinoza, Fechner, Schopenhauer, and others, a number of scientists, notably physicists and psychologists, have explored the dual-aspect route since the mid 20th century. Needless to say, none of their attempts has resolved all aspects of the mind-matter relation. In the following some of these approaches will be presented. The subsequent sections will elaborate on one of them, due to Pauli and Jung, and outline how it may be potentially viable. The notion of complementarity was originally coined by William James (1890, p. 206) and adopted by some psychologists, for instance referring to the bistable perception of ambiguous stimuli. Bohr imported it into physics, originally with the purpose of replacing the term wave-particle duality, in his "Como Lecture" in 1927 (Bohr 1928, p. 566). But his extensive later writings about complementarity make it clear that Bohr's preeminent concern was to extend the idea of complementarity beyond physics. In the same spirit, Pauli (1950, p. 79) advanced the opinion that the "issue of complementarity within physics naturally leads beyond the narrow field of physics to analogous conditions of human knowledge". According to Bernays (1948), there are two different types of complementarity already in quantum physics. One of them refers to incompatible observables, formally grounded in the non-commutativity of corresponding operators acting on quantum states. This non-commutativity entails all kinds of typical quantum features such as superpositions, quantum probabilities, indeterminism, uncertainty relations, and the violation of Bell inequalities... The second kind of complementarity according to Bernays opens up a wider scope. It refers to conceptual issues such as the quantum physical complementarity of wave and particle pictures: Two descriptions are complementary if they mutually exclude each other, yet are both necessary to describe a situation exhaustively. Complementarity in this sense refers to incompatible aspects which cannot be combined in a single description based on a purely Boolean, two-valued logic... The feature of complementarity in a non-Boolean logic means that a proposition and its complement pertain to two aspects of a situation that are incompatible. They are both together necessary to describe the situation exhaustively. Neither one of them alone is sufficient, yet observing one of them in a given empirical context excludes observing the other one in the same context. For a dual-aspect monism, where the underlying domain is neither physical nor mental (cf. Sec. 1.1), complementarity thus implies that either the physical or the mental aspect is accessible in a given empirical context, although both of them are necessary for a complete picture. When Pauli (1952, p. 164) says that "it would be most satisfactory if physis and psyche could be conceived as complementary aspects of the same reality", he proposes a dual-aspect monism precisely in this sense...Atmanspacher describes the Pauli-Jung conjecture in four parts: (1) the relation between local realism and holism in (quantum) physics, One of the central problems, if not the problem, of quantum mechanics is the process of measurement. Although much progress has been achieved with respect to its understanding since the early days of quantum mechanics, the problem is still not completely solved. However, empirical results and modern formulations of quantum theory allow us to state it in a way that is more precise than ever before. From a conceptual point of view, measurement can be viewed as an intervention decomposing a system constituting an inseparable whole into locally separate parts. The empirical cornerstone of our understanding of this decomposition involves so-called nonlocal correlations (Einstein et al. 1935, Bell 1964, Aspect et al. 1982). They are generic in any system requiring a description in terms of non-commuting observables. These correlations can be measured in suitable experiments and indicate post festum that the measured system was in a holistic state before measurement. Conceptually, this means that one can indirectly infer knowledge about an unmeasured state by the result of a controlled intervention into that state due to measurement. At the same time, this controlled intervention entails that the observed system changes its state in a basically uncontrollable way (Bohr 1935). It is tempting to say that such nonlocal correlations correlate everything with everything else, thus suggesting a holistic concept of reality through and through. But this would be misleading without precise qualifications. Quantum holism is only one among two reality concepts that modern quantum theory requires. Equally important is the ('common sense") concept of a local reality which was considered to be the reality for centuries of physicists from Newton to Einstein. As Bohr has emphasized over and over, local realism is unavoidable for a proper description of experiments and their results by Boolean (yes-no) propositions. Today we know that both concepts together are necessary for a comprehensive description of reality, neither of them is sufficient on its own. In the framework of algebraic quantum theory, the dierence between them can be mathematically formalized and clearly understood by two different state concepts: those of ontic and epistemic states... While epistemic states are those states to which epistemic, i.e. empirical access is possible by measurement (and observation in general), ontic states are supposed to characterize the system independent of its observation and our resulting knowledge. One may wonder why it is useful to have an ontic level of description for which empirical (or operational) access is no option at all. However, a most appealing feature at this ontic level is the existence of rst principles and universal laws that are unavailable in an epistemic description. From such an ontic level, it is possible to deduce proper epistemic descriptions given enough details - contexts as it were - about empirically given situations. The distinction of ontic and epistemic states provides an important clue to understand the distinction between a holistic and a local concept of reality. Ontic states and associated intrinsic properties refer to the holistic concept of reality and are operationally inaccessible, whereas epistemic states and associated contextual properties refer to a local concept of an operationally accessible reality. The process of measurement represents the link between the two. Measurement suppresses the connectedness constituting a holistic reality and generates approximately separate local objects constituting a local reality. Although this is a fairly modern picture, it also has a conservative aspect: Conceiving the mind-matter distinction in terms of a splitting of a psychophysically neutral domain implies correlations between mind and matter as a direct and generic consequence. It is important, though, to stress right at the outset that these correlations are not due to causal interactions (in the sense of efficient causation as usually looked for in science) between the mental and the material. In a dual-aspect framework of thinking it would be wrong to interpret mind (or mental states) as directly caused by matter (or material states) or vice versa. Pauli and Jung discussed such correlations extensively in their correspondence between June 1949 and February 1951 when Jung drafted his article on "synchronicity" for the book that he published jointly with Pauli (Jung and Pauli 1952). In a condensed form, two (or more) seemingly accidental, but not necessarily simultaneous events are called synchronistic if the following three conditions are satisfied.1. Each pair of synchronistic events includes an internally conceived and an externally perceived component. 2. Any presumption of a causal relationship between the events is absurd or even inconceivable. 3. The events correspond with one another by a common meaning, often expressed symbolically.The first criterion makes clear that synchronistic phenomena are psychophysical phenomena, intractable when dealing with mind or matter alone. The second criterion repeats the inapplicability of causation in the narrow sense of a conventional cause-and-effect-relation. And the third criterion suggests the concept of meaning as a constructive way to characterize mind-matter correlations. Since synchronistic phenomena are not necessarily temporally "synchronous" (in the sense of "simultaneous"), synchronicity is a somewhat misleading term. For this reason Pauli preferred to speak of "meaningful correspondences" ("Sinnkorrespondenzen") under the influence of an archetypal "acausal ordering". He considered both Jung's synchronicity and the old teleological idea of finality (in the general sense of a process oriented toward a goal) as particular instances of such an acausal ordering which cannot be set up intentionally. In contrast, the mathematical notion of "blind" chance (referring to stochastically accidental events) might be considered as the limiting case of a meaningless correspondence. Similar to their idea of complementary notions of effcient causation and meaningful correspondence, Pauli and Jung discussed a possible complementarity of statistical limit theorems and singular synchronistic events. The upshot of this proposal is that synchronistic phenomena cannot be corroborated by statistical methods as they are usually applied. In a letter to Fierz of June 3, 1952, Pauli wrote (von Meyenn 1996, pp. 634{635):And in his "Lecture to the Foreign People" (Atmanspacher et al. 1995, p. 326), where he sketches some of his ideas about biological evolution, he states his impression thatWhat Pauli here postulates is a kind of lawful regularity beyond both deterministic and statistical laws, based on the notion of meaning and, thus, entirely outside the natural sciences of his time and also, more or less, of today... For the mindset of a psychologist like Jung, the issue of meaning is of primary signicance anyway. For a long time, Jung insisted that the concept of synchronicity should be reserved for cases of distinctly numinous character, when the experience of meaning takes on existential dimensions. With this understanding synchronistic correlations would be extremely rare, thus contradicting their supposedly generic nature. Only in later years, Jung opened up toward the possibility that synchronicity might be a notion that should be conceived as ubiquitous as indicated above (Jung 1969, par. 440):In this regard, the development of Pauli's and Jung's views about archetypes and their role in manifesting synchronicities suggests a distinction between two different kinds of synchronistic events which I suggest to denote as "structural" versus "induced". Structural synchronicity refers to the role of archetypes as ordering factors with a strictly unidirectional influence on the material and the mental (Pauli's letter to Fierz of 1948, see Sec. 2.3). Induced synchronicity refers to the uncontrollable backreaction that changes of consciousness induce in the unconscious and, consequently, in the physical world as well. This way, the picture is extended to a bidirectional relation (Pauli's letter to Jung of 1954). It is important to keep in mind that even in induced synchronicity, not only in structural synchronicity, there is no direct causal relation from the mental to the physical (i.e. no direct "mental causation") or vice versa. The problem of an "interaction" between categorically distinct regimes is thus avoided. Moreover, I should stress that the "meaning" connecting synchronistic events, although being subjectively ascribed (by the experiencing subject), is not completely arbitrary. It depends on the situation as a whole, including conditions that are not consciously available to the subject.
References
|