Bohmian Mechanics
Bohmian Mechanics builds on the 1952 work of
David Bohm, who in turn had recovered some work by
Louis de Broglie in the 1920's, around the time that
Werner Heisenberg's "matrix mechanics" and
Erwin Schrödinger's "wave mechanics" were being formulated.
Following
Albert Einstein of a "
Führungsfeld" or "guiding field," De Broglie interpreted the wave function of quantum mechanics as a "pilot wave" carrying a material particle along with it. De Broglie accepted Einstein's idea, made famous by
Max Born as his "statistical interpretation," that the (square of the) wave function gives us the probability of finding a particle.
The de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave wave goes through both slits in the
two-slit experiment, interfering with itself and accounting for the interference pattern, though the particle enters only through one slit, maintaining its discreteness. Which slit a particle passes through and its ultimate location on the detector are completely
determined by its initial position and the wave function, according to Bohm.
Bohmian mechanics is also known as the "de Broglie-Bohm theory," the "pilot wave theory," and the "causal interpretation" of quantum mechanics. It is a completely
deterministic theory and claims to be completely compatible with and to make exactly the same predictions as standard quantum mechanics. This is hard to believe, because quantum mechanics is
indeterministic, accounting for radioactive decay and the random times and directions of atomic radiative transitions, for example.
It is called "causal" because it is a
deterministic theory, with "hidden variables" suggested by Bohm as "completing" the quantum mechanics that Einstein argued was "incomplete" and "statistical." The hidden variables provide the positions of all the particles as "riding on" the waves at places where the waves have maximum intensity or amplitude.
Bohm thought that known positions would provide the determinacy and explain away the
nonlocal behaviors predicted by
Albert Einstein in his
EPR paper.
John Bell proved that if Bohm's hidden variables did exist, they would still be "nonlocal." They could not restore Einstein's locality.
Bohmian mechanics denies the
"collapse of the wave function," since a collapse is associated with indeterminism. The deterministic Schrödinger equation provides no information that predicts the time, position, or direction of a collapse.
Some physicists who believe that the wave function never collapses, such as
Erwin Schrödinger,
decoherentists like
Dieter Zeh and
Wojczech Zurek, and even
John Bell, even deny the existence or particles and "quantum jumps." Bohm does accept particles, while being somewhat unclear on quantum jumps.
Note that the collapse of the wave function, or "reduction of the wave packet," is one of
Paul Dirac's three fundamental postulates, the others being the
principle of superposition and the
axiom of measurement, also known as the eigenstate-eigenvalue relation.
Bohmian mechanics also denies the role of a "
conscious observer," which has been associated with the
Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum mechanics and was defended by
John von Neumann and
Eugene Wigner.
Bohmian mechanics has a large and enthusiastic following of philosophers of science and theoretical physicists, including
David Z. Albert,
Jeffrey Bub (a student of Bohm),
Jean Bricmont,
Detlef Dürr,
Sheldon Goldstein, and
Tim Maudlin.
They all agree that testable predictions of Bohmian mechanics are identical to those of standard quantum mechanics, so the Bohmian view is only an
interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Bohmian Mechanics Compared to Other Interpretations
|
Bohmian
|
Copenhagen
|
Standard
|
Ensemble
|
Many Worlds
|
Decoherence
|
Information
|
Deterministic
|
Yes
|
Yes
|
No
|
No
|
Yes
|
Yes
|
No
|
Nonlocal
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Collapse
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Observer
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hidden Variables
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Normal |
Teacher |
Scholar