Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Jeremy Butterfield Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins August Compte Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green Niels Henrik Gregersen H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza James Ladyman Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Ernest Nagel Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Xenophon Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Jacob Barandes Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann John Tyler Bonner Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Daniel Brooks Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin William Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Simon Conway-Morris Peter Corning George Cowan Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Paul Davies Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre David Depew Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Dupré John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Walter Elsasser Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier George Fox Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Augustin-Jean Fresnel Karl Friston Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Ernst Haeckel Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg Grete Hermann John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson Ray Jackendoff Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes William Stanley Jevons Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell John Maynard Smith Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Travis Norsen Howard T. Odum Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Robert Rosen Frank Rosenblatt Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Stanley Salthe Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Kenneth Stanley Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing Robert Ulanowicz C. S. Unnikrishnan Nico van Kampen Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Clément Vidal Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington James D. Watson John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg August Weismann Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wiley E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Carl Woese Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium Evo Devo Scholar Talk CCS25 Talk |
Robert Rosen
Robert Rosen was a theoretical biologist whose Ph.D. in mathematical biology was supervised by Nicholas Rashevsky at the University of Chicago.
In his 1985 book Anticipatory Systems: Philosophical, Mathematical, and Methodological Foundations, he defined an anticipatory system, a central element in today's machine learning and artificial intelligence.
A system containing a predictive model of itself and/or its environment, which allows it to change state at an instant in accord with the model's predictions pertaining to a later instant.In his 1991 book Life Itself: A Comprehensive Inquiry Into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of Life, Rosen considers the machine metaphor, mechanisms in general, and complex systems modeled as mathematical machines, i.e., computers. To sum up: the role of the machine metaphor in biology today is as follows. First, It assures the biologist that their subject is an analytical one. because it asserts that any machine is a set of parts. Second, it assures them that the same set of parts will solve all problems of fabrication and of physiology simultaneously. Third, it assures them that nothing happens in biology that is outside the ken of the physical universals (or rather of those fragments of physical universality necessary for the understanding of machines). As to the parts themselves, biologists used to think that they were cells, but today they are molecules. And lf biology is hard, it is simply because there are so many parts to be separated and characterized. This last paragraph encapsulates, I think, the working biologist's view of reductionism. If the machine metaphor, which is its primary mainstay, is even a little bit wrong, then this metaphor itself makes biology infinitely harder than it needs to be. lt makes biology objectively harder, because it transmutes biology into a struggle to reconcile organic phenomena with sets of constituent fragments of unknown relevance to them; it makes biology subjectively harder because biologists have committed themselves to the analysis rather than to the organism. The question "What is life?" is not often asked in biology, precisely because the machine metaphor already answers it: "Life is a machine." Indeed, to suggest otherwise is regarded as unscientific and viewed with the greatest hostility as an attempt to take biology back to metaphysics. This is the legacy of the machine metaphor. l hope to convince the reader, in the course of the present work, that the machine metaphor is not just a little bit wrong; it is entirely wrong and must be discarded. He was also the one who conceived the pregnant idea of stringing excitable elements into networks. He thereby converted what was originally a theory of peripheral nerve into a theory of central nerve, a theory of the brain, which he bolstered by exhibiting simple networks that would discriminate, learn, remember, and do other "intelligent" things. The reader should recall that this was all accomplished in the 1930s. The neural network, the entire field of "artificial intelligence," and much else characteristic of contemporary research owe their very existence to Rashevsky's pioneenng work of these days.In his final chapter Relational Biology and Biology, Rosen writes... Evolution has, as we have seen, come to do for biology today what vitalism did for it previously. Vitalism, in its most general form, simply asserted that whatever made organisms alive was forever out of the reach of what governed inanimate nature. Some additional principle, some vital force, had to be invoked; it was precisely this additional principle, missing from the rest of nature, which made organism in principle inexplicable via inanimate nature alone. In the past, the only perceptible alternative to this vitalism was mechanism; the converse claim that there is nothing in biology which cannot be understood in precisely the same terms in which anything else in nature is understood. As we saw at the outset, the Cartesian Machine Metaphor offered precisely this; a way of anchoring biology in science by demystifying it, and subsuming it entirely into physics. By physics, of course, I mean the contemporary physics of the time; whether in 1650, or in 1950, or today. Both of these positions have had over the years an immense allure to the biologist. Mechanism offers a secure place for biologists in science, as scientists among other scientists; respectability through the adoption of a common, shared tradition and shared principles. They need no longer be dismissed contemptuously as "birdwatchers'' or as mystics. It is very important to biologists to share in this security; to be "inside." On the other hand, biologists have always liked to believe that what they study is somehow different, and hence that they are not just like everybody else. The cost of espousing mechanism was precisely that they give this up. As long as the only alternative seemed to be vitalism, they predominately, though grudgingly, chose the former. Biologists today have come to see in Darwinian evolution a way of distinguishing themselves again, of making themselves separate, without the vitalistic traps. Basically, the argument is now that it is evolution which is unpredictable, non-mechanical, immune to the entailments. the causality, the determinism which mechanism made them espouse, By the single, simple act of redefining biology, to assert that it is about evolution rather than about organism, we can in effect have our mechanistic cake, and eat our vitalistic one too, Biologists continue to espouse a most narrow form of mechanism as far as what goes on within organisms is concerned. But if biology is about evolution, these mechanistic shackles can be devalued; conceptually assigned a subordinate role. One can (at least apparently) embrace evolution without having to deny mechanism; but we can thereby devalue it. To avoid making evolution subject to mechanism is therefore essential. But it is also essential to avoid asserting anything vitalistic. The only way to do this is to deny any vestige of entailment in evolutionary processes at all. By doing so, we tum evolution, and hence biology, into a collection of pure historical chronicles, like tables of random numbers, or stock exchange quotations. This absolute denial of entailment in evolutionary processes is thus a central, perhaps the central pillar, of the current biological weltanschauung. If we did admit entailment into the evolutionary realm, then only two alternatives seem visible: (1) these entailments are themselves mechanistic, in which case biology disappears back into mechanism again, and loses forever its distinguished character, or (2) these entailments are not mechanistic, which seems to mean they must be Vitalistic again. Both of these, for different reasons, are quite unacceptable. Hence we are driven to expunge entailment from evolution entirely, not on any intrinsic scientific grounds, but because of the psychological requirements of biologists. This picture struck me early as a kind of mythology, with evolution as protagonist, in its exact dictionary meaning of "serving to explain or sanctify some concept, usage, institution or natural phenomenon."... This, then, is the paradox of evolution - that it has come to play an essential mythological role in the world-picture of contemporary biologists. It was initially regarded as a way to bring the panorama of biological species into the realm of science. Its present role is rather, to excuse itself from science through its absolute denial of evolutionary entailrnents, and thereby to consign itself (and hence biology, as presently constituted) to the realm of historical chronicle. However, as we have abundantly argued in the preceding pages, it is not a question of mechanism or vitalsm. It is a question of simplicity or complexity.Normal | Teacher | Scholar |