Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Tom Clark
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
U.T.Place
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
John Duns Scotus
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
David Shiang
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
Peter Slezak
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Augustin-Jean Fresnel
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Werner Loewenstein
Hendrik Lorentz
Josef Loschmidt
Alfred Lotka
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
A.A. Roback
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Robert Sapolsky
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
C. S. Unnikrishnan
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Vladimir Vernadsky
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Jeffrey Wicken
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
Daniel Pollen

Daniel Pollen is a neuroscientist who specializes in visual perception. In his 2011 work, "On the Emergence of Primary Visual Perception," he revises his model for primary visual perception (PVP) to help identify the links between aspects of perceptual experience and their neural representations. He also explores a minimal model of self that can be built onto these links and assume ownership of the related experiences.
A Conceptual and Biological Framework for Primary Visual Perception
Our basic hypothesis is that primary visual perception (PVP) depends upon both intact early visual areas and intact specific high-order parietal areas. However, to make this hypothesis more precise, to distinguish it from related models, and to make it amenable for critical testing require more elaboration. This is especially so given the numerous controversies already extant in this field. Moreover, many discussions of perception have been hindered by multiple definitions of perceptual experience and difficulties distinguishing perceptual phenomena from high-level cognitive processes. Consequently, we seek to identify those neural networks that subserve PVP...

There is currently an insurmountable gap between identifying the neural representations that correlate with perceptual experience and for accounting for such experience itself. If we want to narrow that gap, we may attempt to identify the minimal necessary requirements for perceptual experience because then we will have identified the minimal gap that needs to be closed. We see our reductionistic approach to PVP as itself a novel one that complements the more general approach to the "neural correlates of consciousness" (Crick and Koch 1995) and the global workspace and neuronal workspace models of Baars (1989) and Changeux and Dehaene (2008), respectively.

As a first step toward our objectives, we identify those cortical areas and their subcortical dependencies required for representations of our most basic visual percepts within a self-referential context. This is to suggest that image representations are linked to neural representations of at least a minimal self with a sense of perceptual ownership in order to establish a personal experience of the images and underlying objects.

However, the applicability of this framework extends beyond the obvious linkage of self and world by attention. For example, functions that build upon attentional selection such as intention and decision making also require a link to self either for ownership of the process and/or for its execution. The present work builds upon many pertinent advances in the basic neurobiological, neurological, neuroanatomic, and cognitive neuroscientific literatures as most relevant to the issues at hand. We intend that this conceptual framework for PVP will facilitate interactions between the above disciplines and with neuropsychology and philosophy alike and also be of interest to those who share in the quest for the basis of perceptual experience...

Pollen's work has researched the importance of afferent and efferent neural loops exhibiting feedback and feedforward between the primary visual cortical areas.
Recursive Loops
Theorists generally have assumed, supported by the above anatomic evidence, that afferent and recurrent streams of neuronal activity seek mutually reinforcing matches within sequences of cortical areas (Milner 1974; Grossberg 1976; Edelman 1978; Koch 1987; Damasio 1989; Mumford 1992; Ullman 1995; Pollen 1999). Such neural activity may be either stimulus specific or task dependent and likely employs both recurrent corticocortical and cortico-pulvinar--cortical projections (Shipp 2004). Even a single bottom-up top-down cycle of neural activity may remove substantial ambiguities in object recognition almost simultaneously at multiple cortical levels (Ephshtein et al. 2008).

There are abundant reasons to suggest that recurrent projections within both the ventral and dorsal loops participate in perceptual experience. For review, please see Pollen (1999). One of the proposals that seems indispensable for reconciling perceptual experience and its dependence on figure-ground segregation as a precondition for object recognition within the ventral loop is that of Grossberg (1994) and Mumford (1994). These authors suggest that figure-ground separation and object recognition cannot progress in the simple bottom-up serial fashion but must occur iteratively within recursive loops.

Pollen considers various definitions for a minimal self that can be attentive to particular loops.
Minimal Self
We now attempt to relate the normal aspects of processing described above to an associated sense of self as one requisite for the emergence of PVP. Neisser (1988) defined the most primitive sense of self in relationship to the immediate physical environment as the "ecological self." Neisser’s qualifier was motivated by Gibson’s development of "ecological optics" Gibson (1961) specifying how an animal registers the information about the environment inherent in both stationary and moving optic arrays. Gibson (1979) also proposed that perceiving requires the "coperceiving of self."

Gallagher (2000) incorporates Neisser’s ecological self within his own broader definition of a prereflective prelinguistic "minimal self." Gallagher’s minimal self is implicit accepting the givenness of a first-person perspective. Such a perspective is never "a view from nowhere" but rather is always defined "by its relationship to the perceiver’s body which concerns not simply location and posture but action in pragmatic contexts. . ." Gallagher (2006).

Neural Correlates of Perceptual Experience
All current models generally assume that each subjective phenomenal experience is a consequence of a unique neural state (Crick and Koch 1995). This conclusion is consistent with the present model, that of Tononi and Edelman (1998) and Tononi (2008) on ‘‘consciousness as integrated information,’’ the ‘‘neural stance’’ model of Lamme (2006), and the ‘‘central representation’’ model of Taylor (2001, 2007). These models also assume hierarchical and recurrent processing. See also Block (2009).

However, in other respects, these models derive from different sets of primary principles. Our hypothesis differs from other current models primarily in its objective to define the anatomical and functional correlates for the minimally definable entity of PVP.

Tononi (2008) builds upon a very abstract assumption of consciousness as highly integrated information and proceeds to elaborate models to quantitate the information content of higher perceptual functions based upon this assumption. If future such models become increasingly related to functionally entities, it will be of interest to learn whether and how their predictions will converge or diverge with those of the present approach.

The view of Lamme (2006) that recurrent processing either is equivalent to consciousness or a surrogate marker for it is consistent with but goes beyond my earlier proposal (Pollen 1999) that dynamic incongruities must be resolved both within and between ascending and descending streams as a condition for the emergence of perceptual experience. I did not equate recurrent processing in itself with consciousness but rather considered recurrent processing as a means to achieve a consensus of neuronal activity across ascending and descending pathways.

Our primary objective here differs from that of global workspace models (Baars 1989; Changeux and Dehaene 2008) in one major respect. We do not doubt that neuronal activity in the posterior perceptual core can gain entry to the global workspace and, in turn, be influenced by it. However, we believe that the evidence reviewed here suggests that selective activation within the posterior core, in itself, is sufficient to engender primary visual experience. If we are correct, then the quest for the basis for the emergence of PVP reduces to consideration of a substantially smaller set of anatomic and functional entities than is encompassed by the entire global workspace...

Conclusions
We have attempted to define the most basic level of our subjective visual experiences and in identifying their anatomical neural correlates and related functional properties. The model is consistent with the deficits in PVP after injury to V1/ V2 and the specific visual agnosias that occur after lesions of higher extrastriate areas in the ventral loop. The model is also consistent with the known sources of spatial attention and intention in the dorsal loop and the corresponding contralateral inattentional hemispatial neglect syndromes with respect to specific egocentric reference frames after inferior parietal lobe injury. Above all, our model appears to accommodate within in a single concise conceptual framework, an appreciable range of experimental observations arising from diverse neuroscientific disciplines.

The present model also provides a challenge for future studies to determine whether any additional anatomic and functional entities beyond the posterior perceptual core are required for the emergence of PVP. Our analysis has not identified the mechanism by which such subjective experience itself emerges but has defined plausible neural substrata and functional conditions required for such emergence and thus has drawn increased focus to accounting for PVP itself. In identifying the minimal requirements for PVP or at least something close to such requirements—we have narrowed the gap that needs to be closed between identifying the requirements for perceptual experience and for accounting for such experience itself.

The Libet Experiments
A special issue of Consciousness and Cognition in June 2002 was devoted to Benjamin Libet's experiments showing a long delay between cortical stimulation and conscious awareness of the stimulus. Especially controversial was Libet's notion of the backward referral in time of the felt stimulus. One contributor to the 2002 issue, Susan Pockett, claimed that "it takes only 80ms (rather than 500ms) for stimuli to come to consciousness and that "subjective back-referral of sensations in time" to the time of the stimulus does not occur (contrary to Libet's original interpretation of his results).

Backward time referral is still taken literally by neuroscientist Stuart Hameroff. Penrose-Hameroff Orch-OR "backward time referral of quantum information can provide real-time conscious causal control of voluntary actions."
In 2004, Pollen's research in the 1970's was cited by Pockett to show that Benjamin Libet's idea of a long delay between direct cortical stimulation and the moment of conscious awareness was a consequence of suppression of neuronal activity. Libet's interpretation of the delay as "subjective backward time referral" was thereby discounted (by Susan Pockett, among others).

Pollen himself as early as 1999, had questioned Libet's interpretation of the latencies.

Evidence that a sufficiently long duration of steady state activity is an essential requirement for the emergence of phenomenal experience has heen provided Libet (1991), who has shown that trains of repetitive stimuli which engender phenomenal experience require a longer duration than those that evoke unconscious detection above chance levels. Although earlier work by Libet (1964), based in part upon direct electrical stimulation of the human somatosensorv cortex near threshold, suggested that several hundreds of milliseconds of repetitive stimulation was required before phenomenal experience was achieved, other work on direct electrical stimulation of the feline striate cortex (Pollen, 1977) has shown that most striate neurons are silent during the first several hundred milliseconds of stimulation. Thus, the extremely long latencies originally suggested by Libet may be attributed to inhibitory processes prior to the activation of those neuronal assemblies that engender percepts. Even so, his major conclusion regarding the longer stimulus durations required to engender phenomenal experience compared to those for unconscious detection seems secure.

Whether the longer lime duration required for the emergence of the phenomenal state is itself the key requirement for the emergence of visual experience or is a marker for more intense levels of activity within some neuron, neuronal component or local circuit as a consequence of the greater opportunities for temporal summation that accompany such steady conditions remains an open question. In either case, the fundamental mechanism by which these changes may be achieved may be multiplicative or nonlinear effects on the control of contrast gain of afferent activity by efferent activity as has been recently demonstrated for the effects of V1 on LGN neurons (Przybyszewski et al. 1998). If such a similar mechanism holds at cortical levels, then the next steps at further discerning the necessary neural correlates of phenomenal experience may depend upon resolving what the differences are between states accompanying phenomenal experience and those that are subthreshold for it within individual cortical modules. It is not yet obvious that it will be possible to define sufficient conditions for phenomenal experience unless and until we achieve an understanding of such perception itself.

In 2004, Pockett wrote an article in Consciousness and Cognition on "the death of 'subjective backwards referral'." She said that Pollen's "evidence so seriously undermines the data interpretation underlying the notion of subjective backwards referral that it may well have finally buried it."

In the same issue of Consciousness and Cognition, Pollen commented on those who agreed with his analysis of Libet's 1964 paper,

Thus, I believe that our results are consistent with the insights of those who have long suspected a prolonged integrative mechanism and a delayed neuronal activation following threshold direct cortical stimulation Churchland (1981a, 1981b), Glynn (1990, 1991), Gomes (1998, 2002), and especially Pockett (2002), who correctly surmised the existence of a dynamic intratrain facilatory process that we have confirmed at the single cell level. The relationship between intratrain facilitation and a prolonged latency at liminal currents is straightforward. As long as such facilitation is present, it will always be possible to excite a neuron at a lower current than would be required to elicit an action potential with the very first stimulus but only after a sufficient delay for the threshold to be reached.

Pockett (2002) also correctly surmised that no "antedating of conscious experience" is necessary to account for the result of Libet (1993) in the specific case where a peripheral stimulus is experienced before a cortically activated experience via the opposite hemisphere because the cortical activation of adequate neuronal activity is simply delayed. Our results, of course, provide no direct evidence against Libet’s hypothesis for the existence of a subjective back-referral of the onset of conscious experience to the onset of a stimulus in other experimental situations or in natural vision. What our studies do show in this respect is simply that analysis of this issue must take into account that the onset of neuronal activity after threshold direct cortical stimulation for a long train cannot be assumed to begin with the onset of surface stimulation...

Our human results also suggest that the long window of 350–500 ms before conscious experience that appears after threshold cortical stimulation of the striate cortex is also due to the prolonged latency for activation of the underlying cortical neurons. Thus, these results are not indicative of any excessively long central processing time for the emergence of conscious experience after direct cortical stimulation as Libet (1964, 1973, 1993, 2003) has proposed.

References
  • Unpublished papers of Daniel Pollen on ResearchGate

  • "On the Emergence of Primary Visual Perception," Cerebral Cortex September 2011, 21, pp.1941-1953

  • "Fundamental Requirements for Primary Visual Perception," Cerebral Cortex September 2008, 18, pp.1991--1998

  • "Brain stimulation and conscious experience," Consciousness and Cognition 2004, 13, pp.626–645

  • "Explicit Neural Representations, Recursive Neural Networks and Conscious Visual Perception," Cerebral Cortex August 2003;13, pp.807–814

  • "On the Neural Correlates of Visual Perception," Cerebral Cortex Jan/Feb 1999;9, pp.4-19

  • "Alpha Rhythms and Eye Movements in Eidetic Memory," Nature vol 237, May 12 1972 pp.109-112

  • "Response of single neurons to electrical stimulation of the surface of the visual cortex," Brain Behavior and Evolution, 1977, 14, pp.67–86

  • "Some perceptual effects of electrical stimulation of the visual cortex in man," In D. B. Tower (Ed.), The Nervous System, 1975 Vol. 2, pp. 519–528. New York: Clinical Neurosciences, Raven Press.

For Teachers
For Scholars

Chapter 1.5 - The Philosophers Chapter 2.1 - The Problem of Knowledge
Home Part Two - Knowledge
Normal | Teacher | Scholar