Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Mohrhoff-Stapp Debate on 18 "Errors"
Ulrich Mohrhoff reacted to Henry Stapp's 2001 article "Quantum Theory and the Role of Mind in Nature with the claim that it contained 18 errors, primarily the result of misunderstandings or misinterpretations of standard quantum mechanics and its application to mental causation. (See "Mohrhoff on Stapp.")
Stapp was generous in answering Mohrhoff's biting criticism with a fine sense of humor. He takes Mohrhoff's 18 error claims as generating a Buddhist "18-fold way" which result in 18 questions with 18 possible right (Yes/No) answers. Stapp worries that he has only one chance in 250,000 of getting the answers all right (2-18). (See "Stapp on Mohrhoff.")
The Three Papers
Henry Stapp: Quantum Theory and the Role of Mind in Nature
Ulrich Mohrhoff: The World According to Quantum Mechanics (Or, the 18 Errors of Henry P. Stapp)
Henry Stapp: The 18-Fold Way
1. Assigning Probabilities
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (1): "an algorithm for assigning
probabilities to the possible results of possible
measurements cannot also represent an evolving state of
affairs"
Stapp: "But a successful probability algorithm must have a basis in a state of
affairs. A theory that provides an explanation of that basis, or at least
a rationally coherent possible explanation of that basis, is more satisfactory
than just the algorithm alone, because an explanation can point beyond what
is currently known. That is why many scientists seek not just algorithms but
also explanations and understanding."
We interpret Mohrhoff as saying that a Dirac superposition of possible states does not describe actual states. The superposition depends on the choice of basis set. By the Wittgensteinian phrase "state of affairs," Mohrhoff means a "fact," citing the dictionary definition - "a thing that is known to have occurred, to exist, or to be true; a datum of experience; an item of verified information; a piece of evidence." The proper basis for making experimental predictions depends on the "free choice" (Stapp calls it the Heisenberg Choice) of the experimenter as to "which question to ask of Nature" (which experiment to do). And Stapp accepts that the answer that Nature provides is indeterministic, the result of Nature's "Dirac choice," involving the random collapse of the wave function. Mohrhoff is correct that we must distinguish possibilities, with their probabilities that quantum mechanics helps us to calculate, and the actuality of an ontological fact. Mohrhoff knows that ontological facts are objective and independent of any observer, whereas epistemological facts are subjective and depend on observers.
2. Quantum Mechanics and Consciousness
Mohrhoff: Stapp capitalizes on von Neumann’s formulation and interpretation
of QM as a theory of the objective world interacting
with human consciousness. The unobserved
world evolves according to a dynamical equation such
as the Schrödinger equation, while observations cause “a
sudden change that brings the objective physical state
of a system in line with a subjectively felt psychical reality”. This makes QM “intrinsically a theory of mind–matter interaction,” and more specifically a theory
“about the mind–brain connection.”
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (2.1): "The introduction of consciousness... [is] gratuitous.”
Stapp: The empirical basis of science consists of relationships between our conscious
experiences. Thus an essential part of any physical theory is a description
of the connection between the mathematical formulas and the conscious
experiences that are both their empirical basis and the link to possible applications.
For quantum theory, as formulated by its founders, the most profound
departure from prior science was the introduction of ‘the observer’ into
the theory in a nontrivial way. The founders certainly would have avoided
this radical innovation if they had been able to conceive of a satisfactory
way to do so. But they could not. The introduction into the theory of the
experiences of the observer seemed to be needed to define the ‘facts’ that
science had to deal with.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (2.5): “If the answer (to the question does physics presuppose conscious
observers) is negative for classical physics then it is equally negative for
quantum physics.”
Stapp: Our conscious experiences play no dynamical role in classical physics:
they enter only as passive witnesses to events that are determined by local
physical laws. Whether the same is true in the quantum universe cannot be
inferred from analogy to the classical approximation. For there is no analog
in the classical approximation to the lack of determination by contemporary
laws of quantum theory of which question will be posed, or put to nature.
That is, there is in quantum dynamics not only the indeterminateness associated
with the familiar stochastic element, but also the need to define,
in connection with each actual fact, a particular question that was put to
nature. This question is not fixed by the known laws of quantum theory. So
this issue of the ontological character of the ‘facts’, and of the process that
fixes them, makes quantum physics potentially ontologically different from
classical physics: ideas suggested by the classical approximation need not
suffice in the real world.
Stapp is correct that all human knowledge is based on observations (by conscious observers). But this does not mean that the universe is dependent on conscious observers for everything that happens. Many "facts" - the origin of the universe, the origin and evolution of our sun and planets, the beginning of life - were ontological and objective long before human observers made them subjective and epistemological. No knowledge can be gained by a "conscious observer" unless new information has already been irreversibly recorded in the universe. That information can be created and recorded in either the target quantum system or the measuring apparatus. Only then can it become knowledge in the observer's mind
3. Possibilities, Probabilities, Actuality
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (3.1): “A possibility is not the kind of thing that persists and changes in
time.”
Stapp: But a propensity, or disposition [my words] can be a function of time. And
the propensities for various events to occur can change when some event occurs:
the propensity for an earthquake to occur is higher when an earthquake
has very recently occurred. In a universe (or theory) with stochastic elements
the notion of time-dependent propensities can make sense.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (3.2): “the "third error... is a category mistake. It consists of ... treating
possibilities as if they possessed an actuality of their own.”
Stapp: Sir Karl Popper and Werner Heisenberg both recommended treating
quantum probabilities as propensities: i.e., as absolutely existing tendencies
or ‘potentia’ for quantum (actualization) events to occur. This notion has a
long history in philosophy that dates back to Aristotle.
Stapp is right that possibilities and probabilities change with time. This does not make them actualities. When one possibility becomes actuality, the probabilities for all the other possibilities go instantaneously to zero in all the parts of space where an instant earlier they had definite values. [Note that in quantum mechanics these are complex probability amplitudes with both positive and negative values, allowing them to create interference with themselves.]
4. Possibilities, Probabilities, and Popperian "Propensities."
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (4): “the erroneous notion that possibilities are things (“propensities”) that
exist and evolve in time.”
Stapp: Within von Neumann’s formulation of quantum theory the quantum probabilities
can be consistently interpreted as propensities that exist and evolve
in time.
5. Quantum Mechanics and Special Relativity
Mohrhoff: It is well known that the statistical regularities with
which QM is concerned are consistent with SR, while
von Neumann’s interpretation of states as evolving, collapsible
states of affairs is not. Stapp tries to reconcile
SR with von Neumann’s interpretation by giving “special
objective physical status” to a particular family
of constant-time hypersurfaces: State reductions occur
globally and instantaneously with respect to this family
of hypersurfaces. He offers two arguments purporting
to support the existence of a “dynamically preferred sequence
of instantaneous ‘nows’ ”. The first invokes
astronomical data that, incontestably, indicate the existence
of a (cosmologically) preferred sequence of “nows.”
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (5) : “astronomical data...support the existence of a historically preferred
family of hypersurfaces, but not of a dynamically preferred one.”
Stapp: The empirically preferred surfaces are generally believed to be created by
‘inflation’, which is a dynamical process.
7. Information "Transfers" and Special Relativity
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (7): “fallacious... proof of... faster-than-light information transfers of information.”
Stapp: Mohrhoff’s description of my proof
bears little resemblance to my proof itself: there is no buttressing: no second
proof. There is one concise and rigorous proof.
There are instantaneous changes in probability amplitudes (wave functions) in nonlocality demonstrations (see EPR). But there is no physical transfer of material or energy when wave functions collapse. Only abstract information changes (see collapse of the wave function).
8. Free Will (as the experimenter's "free choice")
Mohrhoff:
According to Stapp, granting free will to experimenters
leads to a physical reality inconsistent with the “block
universe” of special relativity (SR), a reality that unfolds
in response to choices. This is one (ε8) of a cluster of
misconceptions arising from the erroneous notion that
the experiential now, and the temporal distinctions that
we base on it, have anything to do with the physical
world (ε9). Objectively, the past, the present, and the
future exist in exactly the same atemporal sense. There
is no such thing as “an evolving objective physical world”
(ε10), and there is no such thing as an objectively open
future or an objectively closed past (ε11). The results of
performed measurements are always “fixed and settled.”
What is objectively open is the results of unperformed
measurements.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (8.1): “granting free will to experimenters” does not lead “to a physical
reality inconsistent with the ‘block universe’ of SR.
Stapp: By free will I mean the freedom to will ourselves to act ‘now’ either in
some particular way, or not in that way. The existence of freedom in this
sense is incompatible with the ‘block universe’ of SR, which says that the
whole universe is laid out for all time in the way that SR (classical special
relativity theory) ordains, i.e., such that given the physical state of the universe
for very earlier times there is no possibility of choosing now to act in
some way or to not act in that way. But the laws of quantum mechanics,
being dynamically incomplete, do not entail a block universe in the way that
the deterministic and complete laws of SR do. The generally accepted application
of the requirements of the theory of relativity to quantum theory
is to its predictions: they must conform to the no-faster-than-light requirements
of the theory of relativity. This is exemplified by Tomonaga-Schwinger
relativistic quantum field theory, which is completely compatible with instantaneous
collapses along spacelike surfaces, and in fact demands such collapse
to the extent that one accepts the existence of von Neumann’s Process I. The
laws of quantum theory lack the coercive quality of the classical laws that
entail the block universe.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (8.2): ”if the possibility of foreknowledge does not exist,..I can actually be
a free agent.”
Stapp: Not in the sense that I have described, in a universe in which the deterministic
laws of SR hold. For being free in that sense means being free to act
in either one of two different ways in a universe with a given fixed past. No
such freedom exists in a universe that obeys the deterministic laws of special
relativity. What the person knows, or does not know, is not pertinent to that
conclusion.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (8.3): “The fact that the future in a sense ‘already’ exists is no reason why
choices made at an earlier time cannot be partially responsible for it.”
Stapp: The ‘choices’ actually made at an earlier time can certainly be partially
responsible for what happens later. But in a world that conforms to the
deterministic laws of classical of SR, and with a fixed early universe, that
‘choice’ made at the earlier time is not ‘free’: it could not go in either one of
two different ways. “Freedom”, in this sense is not compatible with the block
universe of SR, but it is compatible with von Neumann quantum theory, due
to the indeterminacy within that theory of which question will be put to
nature.
Mohrhoff and Stapp appear to be talking at cross purposes here?
12-13. Classical and Quantum Causation
Mohrhoff: Causality,
as Hume discovered two and a half centuries ago,
lies in the eye of the beholder. While classical physics permits
the anthropomorphic projection of causality into the
physical world with some measure of consistency, quantum
physics does not. Trying to causally explain the
quantum-mechanical correlations is putting the cart in
front of the horse. It is the correlations that explain why
causal explanations work to the extent they do. Stapp’s
attempt to involve causality at a more fundamental level
(ε12) depends crucially on his erroneous view that the
factual basis on which quantum-mechanical probabilities
are to be assigned is determined by Nature rather than
by us (ε13).
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (12): The “attempt to involve causality at a more fundamental level” is an
error. “While classical physics permits the anthropomorphic projection of
causality into the physical world with some measure of consistency quantum
physics does not.”
Stapp: I am not projecting the intuition of the causal power of our thoughts
into the world to explain the deterministic aspect of nature associated with
the Schroedinger equation. I am concerned rather with explaining how our
thoughts themselves can be causally efficacious. The mathematical fact is
that the quantum laws allow this, by virtue of the indeterminacy associated
with von Neumann’s Process I, (The freedom of choice in which question to
pose — i.e., the basis problem) whereas the classical laws do not provide or
allow an analogous causal efficacy. In classical theory the future is determined
by the past by LOCAL laws, whereas in quantum theory a present choice of
which question to pose is not determined by the local laws of contemporary
physics.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (13): “Error 12 depends crucially upon ...[the] erronous view that the factual
basis on which quantum probabilities are to be assigned is determined by Nature rather than by us.”
Stapp: One of my very chief points is that quantum theory is incomplete because
the equations of quantum theory do not specify which question is put to Nature,
i.e., which apparatus is put in place, which ‘basis’ is used to determine
a ‘fact’. That role is given to us, the observer/participants, by Copenhagen
quantum theory. In von Neumann’s formulation this choice is bound up in
the psycho-physical event specified by Process I. That this freedom of choice
of basis, is given to “us”, is the key point that I exploit to explain how
mental effort can influence brain activity. Mohrhoff and I seem to be in basic
agreement on this essential point.
So Stapp does not in fact take the "opposite" position from Mohrhoff on everything. What Stapp sometimes calls the "Heisenberg Choice" is a free act. (Von Neumann's Process 1, which Stapp calls the "Dirac Choice," the choice made by Nature, is indeterminate.) It is not clear that either Stapp or Mohrhoff see clearly how - first - quantum indeterminism, then - second - an "adequate" determinism combine to make human freedom possible.
15-18. Mental Causation
Mohrhoff: Stapp’s account of mental causation,
and a number of further errors (not all enumerated)
are pointed out, such as: The objective brain can (sometimes)
be described as a decoherent mixture of “classically
described brains” all of which must be regarded as
real (ε16).Crucial to Stapp’s account is the metaphor of
the experimenter as interrogator of Nature. Within the
Copenhagen framework, which accords a special status
to measuring instruments, this is a fitting metaphor for
a well-defined scenario. In Stapp’s framework, which accords
a special status to the neural correlates of mental
states, it is not (ε17). Its sole purpose is to gloss over
the disparity between physical experimentation and psychological
attention. Once this purpose is achieved, the
metaphor is discarded, for in the end Nature not only
provides the answers but also asks the questions. The
theory Stapp ends up formulating is completely different
from the theory he initially professes to formulate (ε18),
for in the beginning consciousness is responsible for state
vector reductions, while in the end a new physical law is
responsible, a law that in no wise depends on the presence
of consciousness.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (15): “freedom to choose is a classical phenomenon.”
Stapp: Mohrhoff’s argument is based on his idea that mental choice and effort
must be coercive, rather than dispositional. But quantum theory allows dispositional
causes. And within classical physical theory there is no possibility
of freedom of the kind that I have described above. But von Neumann quantum
theory does allow that sort of freedom.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (16): It is erroneous to claim that “The objective brain can (sometimes) be described as a decoherent statistical mixture of ‘classically described brains’
all of which must be regarded as real.”
Stapp: By the objective brain I mean the quantum state defined by taking the
trace of the state (density matrix) of the universe over all variables other than
those that characterize the brain, and my claim is merely that interaction
with the environment converts this state to a form that can be roughly described
as a mixture of states each of which approximates a classical state of
the brain, in the sense that in the position-bases the states are approximately
localized. This mixture includes ALL of these states, not just one of them,
or some small subset that are all observationally indistinguishable. There is
therefore the problem of relating this state to observation. This is achieved,
within the von Neumann formulation, by a psycho-physical event described
by Process I. This approach can be described as taking the mathematics of
quantum theory to give valid information about the structure of reality, and
making our idea of nature, and the facts that define it, conform as closely as
possible to that mathematical description.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (17): “The metaphor of experimenter as interrogator of Nature [is fitting]
within the Copenhagen framework, which accords special status to measuring
instruments, [but is not fitting] in Stapp’s scenario, which accords special
status to neural correlates of mental states.”
Stapp: In the Copenhagen interpretation ‘the measuring instruments and the
participant/observer’ stand outside the system that is described by the quantum
mathematics, and they are probing some property of a ‘measured system’,
which is part of an imbedding quantum universe. In the von Neumann
formulation the role of ‘the measuring instruments and the participant/
observer’ is transferred to the ’abstract ego’, and the measured system
whose properties are being probed is the brain of the observer.
The need for the outside ‘observer’, which includes the measuring devices,
is to specify a definite question, which is represented by a projection operator
P acting on the state of the ‘measured system’, even though nothing about
that system itself— or even the whole of the quantum-described universe—
defines that particular operator P, or specifies when that question is ‘put to
Nature.’
A key technical question now arises: To what extent does the natural
Schroedinger evolution of the brain, abetted by the Environment-Induced-
Decoherence (EID), already decompose the quantum state of the brain into
orthogonal branches that correspond to distinguishable ‘facts’? The EID
tends to create ‘coherent states’, which have exponential tails, and are not
mutually orthogonal. In fact, it is impossible in principle for a Schroedinger
evolution to define the projection operators P that are needed in the von
Neumann formulas. That fact is undoubtedly why von Neumann introduced
his Process I as a basic process not derivable from the Schroedinger Process
II. There is no way to get the needed projection operators out of Process
II. A projection operator defines, and is defined by, a subspace. That means
that the definition of a projection operator P must distinguish every vector in
the subspace from vectors that lie outside that subspace and differ from that
vector by infinitesimal amounts. The Schroedinger evolution of an isolated
system could define and preserve energy eigenstates, but there is no way that
the Schroedinger evolution of a brain interacting with its environment could
specify subspaces associated with experientially distinct facts without some
extra rule or process not specified by the Schroedinger Process II itself. This
fact is the technical basis of von Neumann’s theory. It is this need for some
outside process to fix the content of the facts, and their times of coming into
being, that opens the door to the efficacy of experience.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (17.1): “The questions the mind can put to the brain, by choosing where
to fix its attention, are always compatible, for the mind does not have to
choose between incompatible experimental arrangements.”
Stapp: But it does have to define an operator P, or, equivalently, a subspace of
the Hilbert space associated with the brain, and this subspace is not specified
by the prior (quantum) state of the brain or the universe.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (17.2): “If attention is drawn to the highest bidder, the highest bidder is not a component of a mixture of CDBs (Classically Described Brains), but
one among several neural events or activities competing for attention in one
and the same CDB.”
Stapp: The various CDBs are overlapping (non-orthogonal), and the function
of Process I is to pick out of this amorphous mass of possible states some
well defined subspace associated with a distinct experience. Our ruminations
about possible choices can run over various consciously experienced possibilities,
but each such experience is associated with a selection of a subspace
from the amorphous collection of overlapping possibilities that constitutes
the state of the brain at that moment. The Schroedinger Process II cannot
by itself unambiguously decompose the state of the brain into well defined
orthogonal branches corresponding to distinct CDBs. [Note that Stapp now calls von Neumann Process II the Schrödinger process.]
Mohrhoff: Stapp presents a simple dynamical model of mind–
brain interaction in which “the ‘best possible’ question
that could be asked by the individual at time t,” given
the state S(t) of the universe at this time, is the question
Pmax that maximizes Tr[PS(t)]. This question is
posed when the probability of a positive answer reaches
a relative maximum.
Here Stapp introduces a new physical law, specifying
which question Nature will ask herself next and when she
will do so. Stapp thus effectively proposes a new theory,
as different from standard QM as nonlinear adulterations
of QM. The theory which he ends up formulating
is completely different from the theory he initially professes
to formulate, for in the beginning consciousness is
responsible for state vector reductions, while in the end
a new physical law is responsible — a law that in no wise
depends on the presence of consciousness.
Thus in the end Stapp, like Eccles, fails to account
for mental causation without implying “violations” of the
laws of contemporary physics. Eccles did not introduce
a new physical law, but he allowed the mind to load the
quantum dice in the process of exocytosis, and this is tantamount
to postulating mentally generated local modifications
of physical laws . Stapp introduces a new
physical law specifying which questions Nature asks herself,
and when, and he allows the mind to modify the
rates at which Nature interrogates herself. This, too, is
tantamount to postulating mentally generated local modifications
of a physical law — the very law Stapp himself
has introduced.
Stapp quotes Mohrhoff (18): “The theory Stapp ends up formulating is completely different from
the theory that he initially professes to formulate, for in the beginning consciousness
is responsible for state vector reduction, whereas in the end a new
physical law is responsible, a law that in no wise depends on consciousness.”
Stapp: That example is not my final theory. It was put forward as a simple
model to show how one could, within the general von Neumann framework
that I have developed, produce a dynamically complete theory. It does this
by postulating a new law that resolves in a certain definite way the dynamical
freedom that I have used to make consciousness efficacious.
Mohrhoff suggests that this model violates the quantum laws, but that
is not true: the extra postulated law controls which questions are asked,
and when they are asked, and these are precisely the elements that are not
controlled by the standard quantum laws, and whose indeterminacy, with
respect to those laws, provides the opening for efficacious minds within contemporary
basic physical theory.
The key issue is whether consciousness itself enters the dynamics. This
devolves to the question: What is the ontological source or basis of the
coercive quality of the laws of nature?
My answer is that with respect to the local dynamical process governed
by the Schroedinger equation this question is not worth pursuing: it is the
existence of that mechanical law that matters to us, and inquiry into what
gives that law its coercive quality is unduly speculative. But the same question
is far from meaningless in connection with the collapse process that is
associated with a human conscious experience. This is because the experiences
associated with these collapses are known to us, and are in fact the
only things really known to us. Thus they are proper elements of science,
and are, in fact, the basis of science.
I have thus emphasized that the resetting (of the state of the brain) associated
with a conscious human experience is mathematically and dynamically
different from the local mechanical (Schroedinger) process, and I now suggest
that the coerciveness of the laws that govern the creation of a stream of consciousness
comes in part from the experiences that constitute that stream:
that the experiential realities are actually doing something that is not done
by the local mechanical laws. Why else would they exist?
Thus I have noted that some process beyond the local mechanical process
described by the Schroedinger equation is needed to complete basic contemporary
physical theory, and tie it to the empirical facts, and I am suggesting that the conscious experiences that emerge in this process are essential
causal elements of a nonlocal evaluative process that is needed to complete
the quantum dynamics.
In summary, local mechanical process alone is logically incapable picking
the question (choosing the basis) and fixing the timings of the events in the
quantum universe. So there is no rational reason to claim that the experiential
reality that constitutes a stream of consciousness is not a causal aspect
of the dynamical process that prolongs or extends this reality, yet lies beyond
what the local quantum mechanical process is logically able to do.
What Stapp's argument comes down to is that Nature alone can never choose a basis set on its own. This he reserves to the power of conscious observers who can exercise their free (Heisenberg) choices. Henry Stapp has been generous in answering Mohrhoff's biting criticism with a fine sense of humor. He takes Mohrhoff's 18 error claims as generating a Buddhist "18-fold way" which result in 18 questions with 18 possible right (Yes/No) answers. Stapp worries that he has only one chance in 250,000 of getting the answers all right (2-18). These long odds (probabilities) might be the case if
|