Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Hans Kornhuber (1928-2009) and Lüder Deecke (1938-)
When you are saying: “Indeed an earlier slow and very slight rise in the readiness potential can be seen as early as 1.5 sec before the action.” this is indeed so. This is the BP1, the bilaterally-symmetrical early BP/RP component generated by both SMAs. The SMA is on the mesial surface of the hemisphere, behind it is the M1/Area 4 of the lower extremity leg and foot. So both SMAs are contributing to BP 1, and this is so even with unilateral movements. This is why we named the potential readiness potential, because this makes the brain ready for the intended movement or action. And we later found the full explanation, I mean why this is so important, so early, and so necessary. Hans Kornhuber and I postulated that there has to be a CMA as well, and made sure there is. CMA means cingulate motor area, and the cingulate gyrus (cingulum is belt) you can look it up on brain maps. This is our emotional brain. It is like a belt running from anterior to posterior on the inner surface of the hemispheres around the corpus callosum (black). I labelled SMA and CMA into Karl Kleist’s brain map, which unfortunately is only available in German.
The Will and Its Brain
Kornhuber and Deecke's 2009 book is a reasoned defense of human free will against those who argue that the fact that the brain is a physical thing must mean that it is totally determined.
The book has a wonderful historical review of the concept of free will, including its twists and turns when twentieth-century behaviorists denied the existence of the mind, which had been the centerpiece of nineteenth-century psychology.
The Preface is well worth reading closely.
Why is it so important that this book appears in English and, what is more, is published in the United States? There are many reasons, here are three of them: (1) To tell the full Bereitschaftspotential story. This slow brain potential, which precedes all our voluntary movements and actions, was discovered by the authors (Kornhuber and Deecke, 1964, 1965). We offered the translated term “readiness potential” in our publication, but the “tongue twister” Bereitschaftspotential (BP) was preferred. The Bereitschaftspotential can be found in the list of German words in the English language. It had quite an impact; it revived the opinion about will and volition and also about freedom as opposed to total determinism. (2) A further discovery is that we have shown experimentally that the frontal lobes are initiating and steering a movement or particular task we perform. But the frontal lobe does not execute the task. It delegates the execution of the task to the expert systems in the brain, mostly to the motor-cortex-basal- ganglia-loop, but in case of visually-guided tracking movements even to the visual cortex itself. The reader of the book will get at least an idea, a feeling, what the human frontal lobes are and what they are doing. As we expound in our book, there is one important statement: The frontal cortex is the seat of the will. This is by no means widely recognized, and the main route of argumentation—what happens when the frontal cortex is destroyed?—is almost forgotten. That is to say, it is essential to incorporate the numerous classical lesion studies in our argumentation. By careful studies of frontal lesions in patients we can leam what the normal functions of the frontal cortex are. This is all classical heritage of Clinical Neurology. It was the discipline of Clinical Neurology that collected the largest body of experience about the abilities of man and his brain. This experience had led to two theories (models) of how the brain functions: (a) a hierarchical system of centers ordered side by side or on top of each other, and (b) a distributed system, in which, by nerve fibers, most of the brain is connected with many other centers, and this system achieves its performances always by distributed cooperation. The two models were heavily debated over decades. But this was on an either-or-basis: “Localisationists” fought against “network advocates.” As the reader will see in the book, we now teach that both principles are realized in higher brains. (3) What then is will? As the present authors conceive it, will is a complex function, beginning with consideration, planning and thereafter, decision, all this taking place in the bright light of consciousness and with self-critical connection to reality, then shifting parts of the processing into unconscious routines but with accompanying supervision, surveillance, control and, if necessary, correction until the goal is reached. We hope that our book may fall on fertile ground: There is a tradition also in the United States, where a movement against total determinism began, promoted by Edward Deci, Frederick Kanfer and others, which revived the tradition of William James, and also by Wayne Hershberger 1989. Deci and Kanfer’s key words are self-regulation, self-determinism and even self-management, terms implying free will. In philosophy too, a new discussion on the will and its freedom began. A book written by Sir Karl Popper and Sir John Eccles discussed the Bereitschaftspotential and Kornhuber’s ideas, and in the “Oxford Handbook of Free Will” the discovery of the Bereitschaftspotential is also discussed (Kane 2002). In the United States it is in particular the philosopher Daniel Dennett, who is writing important books and is an eminent promoter of will evolving in freedom. The reader will find all this in the present book “The Will and its Brain,” he also may consult its index. In the end, he or she may agree with the authors in saying that it is extremely necessary to counteract the dogma of total determinism i. e. that we are totally determined in all our actions and doings. This would have the consequence that we are not responsible for what we are doing. Such an all too easy exculpation (“te absolvo"), some call it “self-corruption” is what people and the media may like to hear. However, it is not so. We do have freedom, inner freedom. Thus, we have responsibility for our deeds, and we can put a veto to bad intentions, e.g. when pursuing unethical goals.
Deecke on "Conscious Will."
The psychologist Daniel Wegner famously argued that the conscious will is an illusion. He and Dan Dennett used the work of Benjamin Libet extensively to defend their determinist views.
But Lüder Deecke explains that early brain activity does not deny human freedom.
Decisions in the brain are mostly not made abruptly—except we are forced by the situation, for instance when skiing—rather they are made gradually. Even simple decisions—for instance the pressing of a right or a left button—need some time and a few seconds go by until we start the movement. The matter is different, if we are under time pressure or with rapt attention to a stimulus. This can be so because we were not yet absolutely determined or because the way from the frontal cortex does not go directly to motor cortex, which was earlier belief, but needs the cooperation of a phylogenetically old subcortical part of the brain that provides learned and stored movement programs, the basal ganglia. Functional magnetic resonance imaging then shows vague activities, which can be interpreted as if up to 10 s prior to the movement in the prefrontal brain a change in activity occurred that might lead to a decision a bit later, i.e., it looks as if an unconscious decision had been made [64]. This is not a sign of a lack of freedom, rather it signals insufficient attention or shortage of memory in conjunction with the absence of haste. The resulting movement is consciously controlled in any case.Normal | Teacher | Scholar |