"People who do not agree with determinism are
usually viewed with suspicion by rationalists who are afraid that if we accept
indeterminism, we may be committed to accepting the doctrine of Free Will,
and may thus become involved in theological arguments about the Soul and
Divine Grace. I usually avoid talking about free will, because I am not clear
enough about what it means, and I even suspect that our intuition of a free
will may mislead us. Nevertheless, I think that determinism is a theory which
is untenable on many grounds, and that we have no reason whatever to accept
it. Indeed, I think that it is important for us to get rid of the determinist
element in the rationalist tradition. It is not only untenable, but it creates endless trouble for us. It is, for this reason, important to realize that indeterminism - that is, the denial of determinism - does not necessarily involve us in any doctrine about our 'will' or about 'responsibility'. (Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, 1962, Harper, 1968, p.123)
"The idea that the only alternative to determinism is just sheer
chance was taken over by Schlick, together with many of his
views on the subject, from Hume, who asserted that
'the removal' of what he called 'physical necessity' must always
result in
'the same thing with chance. As objects must either be
conjoin'd or not, . . . 'tis impossible to admit of any medium
betwixt chance and an absolute necessity'.
"I shall later argue against this important doctrine according
to which the alternative to determinism is sheer chance.
Yet I must admit that the doctrine seems to hold good for the
quantum-theoretical models which have been designed to
explain, or at least to illustrate, the possibility of human freedom. This seems to be the reason why these models are so very
unsatisfactory.
"Compton himself designed such a model, though he did not
particularly like it. It uses quantum indeterminacy, and the
unpredictability of a quantum jump, as a model of a human
decision of great moment. It consists of an amplifier which
amplifies the effect of a single quantum jump in such a way that
it may either cause an explosion or destroy the relay necessary
for bringing the explosion about. In this way one single quantum
jump may be equivalent to a major decision. But in my opinion
the model has no similarity to any rational decision. It is, rather,
a model of a kind of decision-making where people who cannot
make up their minds say: 'Let us toss a penny.' In fact, the
whole apparatus for amplifying a quantum jump seems rather
unnecessary: tossing a penny, and deciding on the result of the
toss whether or not to pull a trigger, would do just as well. And
there are of course computers,with built-in penny-tossing devices
for producing random results, where such are needed.
"It may perhaps be said that some of our decisions are like
penny-tosses: they are snap-decisions, taken without deliberation, since we often do not have enough time to deliberate. A
driver or a pilot has sometimes to take a snap-decision like this;
and if he is well trained, or jug-lucky, the result may be satisfactory; otherwise not.
"I admit that the quantum-jump model may be a model for
such snap decisions; and I even admit that it is conceivable that
something like the amplification of a quantum jump may
actually happen in our brains if we make a snap-decision. But
are snap-decisions really so very interesting? Are they characteristic of human behaviour - of rational human behaviour?
"I do not think so; and I do not think that we shall get much
further with quantum jumps. They are just the kind of examples
which seem to lend support to the thesis of Hume and Schlick
that perfect chance is the only altenative to perfect determinism.
What we need for understanding rational human behaviour
and indeed, animal behaviour is something intermediate in
character between perfect chance and perfect determinism -
something intermediate between perfect clouds and perfect
clocks.
"Hume's and Schlick's ontological thesis that there cannot
exist anything intermediate between chance and determinism
seems to me not only highly dogmatic (not to say doctrinaire)
but clearly absurd; and it is understandable only on the assumption that they believed in a complete determinism in which
chance has no status except as a symptom of our ignorance.
(But even then it seems to me absurd, for there is, clearly, something like partial knowledge, or partial ignorance.)"
(Objective Knowledge, Of Clouds and Clocks, 1972, p. 227ff)