Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Augustin-Jean Fresnel Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
Hilary Bok
Hilary Bok's 1991 Harvard Ph.D. thesis Free Will and Moral Responsibility was later expanded as her 1998 book Freedom and Responsibility. Bok is a compatibilist who thinks that "libertarians should take no comfort from the idea that our actions might be caused by indeterministic natural events." She agrees with Gary Watson that to the extent libertarians hope to explain "our ability to act for reasons, they make it unclear why self-determination requires that our choices be causally undetermined."
Bok was a student of John Rawls at Harvard, and like Rawls, was greatly influenced by the works of Immanuel Kant, especially the Critiques of Pure and Practical Reason, which distinguish matters of truth (epistemology/knowledge) from moral questions (ethics/values). The Critique of Practical Reason includes Kant's attempt to solve the problem of free will. Critics of Kant's solution for freedom, in the face of Newton's deterministic laws of nature, complain that it requires a transcendental realm that Kant called noumenal, which was in some ways an extension of Descartes' mental realm. Both Kant and Descartes locate human freedom in their noumenal/mental realms and consider the dualistic phenomenal/material/bodily realm to be completely governed by deterministic laws. But there are readings of Kant that make human freedom, for him a prerequisite for morality, something entirely inside us, as seen in his famous distinction between the "starry skies above us and the moral law within." Bok focuses on a view of free will and responsibility that is something entirely within us and in some sense independent of natural causal explanations. Bok applies some Kantian concepts, notably the important distinction between pure reason (theory) and practical reason (actual practice), to explain how humans can be free and responsible agents even if determinism is "true." She separates the question of freedom from that of responsibility and does not discuss the conditions under which we should hold persons morally responsible for their conduct. She also wisely separates (and does not discuss) the question of punishment from moral responsibility. For Bok, practical reasoning does not look for causal chains, but looks for the grounds for choices not yet made, and not in a cause-and-effect temporal sequence. The purpose of practical reason is to determine the will, to answer the (Kantian) question "What should I do?" (Theoretical reason answers the question "What can I know?") Bok says that libertarians cannot explain "self-determination" by discovering a theoretical causal chain of events. In any cases, there are many (perhaps infinite numbers of) causes for any event. Which cause is the most important is often a subjective matter. Following Galen Strawson, even if some events in that chain are indeterministic (which she correctly notes means that our actions are not pre-determined from before our birth), discovering all the causes theoretically leaves our selves out of the picture. Quoting Thomas Nagel, she says in causal accounts the 'self' simply disappears. Bok faults libertarians for using theoretical causal chains including indeterministic events to explain free will. They use indeterministic natural events to make our freedom "entirely independent of our purposes, our interests, our reasons and our selves." Only then would freedom exist for them, she says, "Libertarians [should] want to show not only that antecedent events do not determine our conduct but that we do; that our choices are not just indeterministic but self-determined."This is a reasonable criticism. The challenge for libertarians is to show that indeterministic events can break causal chains, as Bok sees clearly, but that in no way do they directly cause our actions. This requires that the indeterminism be limited to the first stage in a two-stage model, where it simply expands the number of alternative possibilities available for evaluation and selection in the second, adequately determined, stage. Bok concludes that the most rudimentary form of freedom is this: "to be free, our wills must be determined by ourselves and not by the external world." Theoretical reason is concerned to provide causal explanations of events. In this case "determined" must be interpreted as "caused." Our choices must be interpreted as "events."With such a theoretical formulation, the problem of free will cannot be solved. We cannot make sense of the problem as long as we assume that the kind of determination in question is causal. Whereas theoretical reasoning is concerned with the causes of events, practical reasoning is concerned with the grounds on the basis of which we choose to act as we do. Practical reasoning constructs a system of reasons that allow us to determine which actions we should perform. Bok says that when we engage in practical reasoning we must use a particular concept of freedom. She argues that "when we act freely in this sense we choose among genuine alternatives, that we should hold ourselves responsible for those acts we freely perform, that we should likewise hold others responsible for their conduct, and that this sort of responsibility differs in kind from mere causal responsibility." She says that the truth of her claims is independent of the truth or falsity of determinism, or any hypothesis about the causes of human action. She says that the problem with libertarian accounts of self-determination derives from their attempt to construe self-determination as a causal property. The practical reasons by which conduct is determined are not temporal, she claims. Thus she does not need to cite earlier and earlier events in a causal chain, though of course such events and their causes are considerations for practical reason. This agrees with the two-stage model view that the alternative possibilities (free thoughts) for willed action are all in existence in the mind at the same time (some indeterministically generated and in that sense "uncaused") for evaluation and selection at the later second stage. Moreover, although the events that cause an action may be external to the mind, the practical reasons that are determining the action cannot be. Justifications for the action (reasons) are independent of any ultimate external natural events (whether deterministic or indeterministic) considered as causes. Bok says we must consider not causal origins but rational grounds, not the causes leading to the action but the reasons that convince her an action is sound. Even if a particular action, the consequence of our practical reasoning, could be described theoretically as the effect of natural causes, we should not regard ourselves as obeying the dictates of some original natural event that controls our lives. She says that the coexistence of theoretical and practical views explains how we can be both fully natural beings and genuinely free and responsible beings. Bok concludes: On the one hand, we want to see our freedom and our dignity as moral agents written into the fabric of the universe for all to see. But on the other, we are unwilling to regard ourselves as worthy of being its sources or its guarantors. We may feel that as purposive agents we are tainted or fickle or untrustworthy; that our freedom is at risk to the extent that it depends on us. We may believe that any conception of ourselves that depends on our practical reasoning could only be a self-aggrandizing distortion or a way of projecting our own desires onto the universe. In either case we would think it an unworthy foundation for our freedom. If we adopt this view, and look to theoretical reasoning for our dignity as free agents, we will find no dignity worth having. But that is only because, in devaluing its source in our practical reasoning, we have already denied it.
Neuroscience and Free Will
In 2007, Bok updated her form of compatibilism against the neuroscientists who may be discovering all the brain mechanisms that underlie our illusion of thinking, reasoning, and acting with a degree of freedom. Her principal references are Michael Gazzaniga and Benjamin Libet.
Bok nicely summarizes the standard argument against free will, if determined, not free, if undetermined, not responsible.
The fundamental problem is as follows. Gazzaniga and Libet both assume that if our choices are causally determined by something, then we are not free. If they are right, then claiming that our choices are due to something nonnatural, like a ‘ghost in the machine’ or a spirit, cannot solve the problem unless that claim allows us to argue that our choices are not causally determined by anything. If, however, our choices are not causally determined by anything, then our choices are not under our control and we are not morally responsible for what we do. Moreover, the idea that our freedom consists in a tendency to make decisions in an indeterministic, uncontrollable way makes it unclear either that we are free, or why we would want to be. |