Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Tom Clark
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
U.T.Place
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
John Duns Scotus
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
David Shiang
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
Peter Slezak
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Augustin-Jean Fresnel
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Werner Loewenstein
Hendrik Lorentz
Josef Loschmidt
Alfred Lotka
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
A.A. Roback
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Robert Sapolsky
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
C. S. Unnikrishnan
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Vladimir Vernadsky
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Jeffrey Wicken
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 
Jeffrey Barrett

Jeffrey Barrett is a philosopher of science at University of California Irvine. He is a major expositor of Hugh Everett's theory of the universal wave function, which Everett and his thesis adviser John Wheeler called the "relative state" formulation of quantum mechanics.

Bryce DeWitt popularized Everett's notion of the universe "splitting" at any measurement-like event. DeWitt said it implies the simultaneous existence of many possible "parallel" worlds, and Everett's work became widely known as the "many-worlds" interpretation of quantum mechanics.

Barrett has published several articles and three books on the Everett interpretation. With writer Peter Byrne, he is a curator of Everett papers at UC Irvine. They compiled The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Collected Works 1955-1980 with Commentary in 2012.

Following Everett, Barrett argues for a logical inconsistency between the two dynamical laws in the standard theory of quantum mechanics:

Barrett says that these two laws are logically inconsistent and that taken together they lead to the problem of measurement:
In the context of the standard theory, the measurement problem results from the fact that the two dynamical laws are mutually incompatible. Since the first is deterministic and continuous and the second is stochastic and discontinuous, no physical system can be governed by both laws simultaneously — indeed, as we shall see, the two laws would typically lead to very different physical states. There is nothing wrong with a theory having mutually incompatible dynamical laws as long as it also provides clear and disjoint conditions for when each correctly describes the evolution of a system, but this is where our loose talk of things behaving one way when someone is looking and another way when no one is looking catches up to us.
In the information interpretation of quantum mechanics, there is a temporal sequence, the deterministic unitary law describes isolated systems (for example, a gas particle in free flight between collisions), the random collapse law describes the interaction during
the next collision.

If information is recorded, the
collision might be a measurement.

The standard theory tells us that the deterministic dynamics describes the evolution of a system unless it is measured, in which case the random dynamics kicks in. But the theory does not tell us what constitutes a measurement. One is left to one's own intuitions concerning what interactions ought to count as measurements. While it turns out that one can typically use such intuitions to get good empirical predictions from the theory, the fact that our intuitions concerning what it takes for an interaction to count as a measurement are ultimately vague means that quantum mechanics is at best ambiguous. Further, if one supposes that measuring devices are ordinary physical systems just like any other, constructed of fundamental particles interacting in their usual deterministic way (and why wouldn't they be?), then the standard theory is logically inconsistent since no system can obey both the deterministic and stochastic dynamical laws simultaneously. This is the measurement problem.

Barrett explains that quantum mechanics is an incomplete theory because it does not tell us which of the possible outcomes of an experiment actually occurs:

If one accepts Everett's model of a good measuring device and if one insists that the usual deterministic linear dynamics always correctly describes the time-evolution of the quantum-mechanical state, then, as we have seen, an ideal observer M who begins in an eigenstate of being ready to measure the x-spin of a system S that is initially in an eigenstate of z-spin will end up in a post-measurement state like

< ψ > = (1 / √2) ( | x-spin up > M | ↑x >S   +   | x-spin down > M | ↓x >S ).

There are several strategies for interpreting | ψ >. One strategy would be to insist that, contrary to what the standard eigenvalue-eigenstate link tells us about | ψ >, there is a single post-measurement observer who has recorded a single determinate measurement result. If this is right, then | ψ > must be an incomplete description of the state of the composite system M + S since it clearly fails to tell us what result M recorded. Further, even if the coefficients on the two terms in the post-measurement superposition (in the determinate-record basis) were different, one would not want to say that the quantum-mechanical state was complete since we know from experience that any term in the post-measurement state with a nonzero coefficient represents a possible measurement record (and the usual quantum-mechanical state would not tell us which term represented the observer's actual record).

It is of the essence of statistical indeterministic theories that the exact outcome cannot be predicted.

In this sense, Einstein was right that quantum mechanics is incomplete. Bohr was too proud to simply accept this fact.

Classical mechanics, with twice as many simultaneously determinate variables (e.g., position and momentum) has twice the information of quantum mechanics.

On this strategy, one would have to supplement the usual quantum-mechanical state description with a parameter that effectively selects one of the terms in the final state (in the determinate-record basis) as the one that correctly describes what result the observer in fact recorded. That is, if one insists that the usual linear dynamics always correctly describes the time-evolution of the quantum-mechanical state and that there is a single post-measurement observer who records a single determinate measurement result, then one is naturally led to abandon the assumption that the quantum-mechanical state provides a complete description of the post-measurement state of the observer and his object system. Given this, one might try to complete the state by (1) choosing a particular physical quantity as always determinate (the path taken by standard hidden-variable theories) or (2) choosing a rule that itself chooses a determinate physical quantity given the current quantum-mechanical state and the system in which one is interested (the path taken by some so-called modal theories). But in either case, one must also have a rule for determining the value of the determinate physical quantity. What quantity is determinate, its value, and the quantum-mechanical state would then together provide a complete physical description of a system at a time.

For Barrett, a "determinate" quantity is one that yields an eigenvalue when measured (it is found in an eigenstate). Otherwise, a quantum system can be in a superposition of states.

the most immediate explanatory demand on quantum mechanics is to explain why we never directly observe a system in a superposition of possessing and not possessing a given property; or, put somewhat differently, quantum mechanics should explain why measurements typically yield determinate measurement records.
In the information interpretation of quantum mechanics, an isolated system S evolves continuously. When it interacts with another system, it jumps instantaneously and randomly to a state of the combined system.

A measurement is not required, only an interaction.

If information is recorded, the
interaction might be a measurement.

The standard explanation replies on the dual structure of the dynamics in the standard collapse formulation of quantum mechanics: (A) if no measurement is made, then a system S evolves continuously according to the linear, deterministic dynamics, which depends only on the energy properties of the system, but (B) if a measurement is made, then the system S instantaneously and randomly jumps to a state where it either determinately has or determinately does not have the property being measured, where the probability of each possible post-measurement state depends on the system’s initial state. While this does explain why measurements typically yield determinate physical records, the dual structure of the dynamics and the occurrence of measurement as an undefined primitive term in the theory is at least curious. Albert Einstein, for one, did not believe that this aspect of the theory could be right.
Barrett tells the story of Einstein saying "Look, I don’t believe that when I am not in my bedroom my bed spreads out all over the room, and whenever I open the door and come in it jumps into the corner."

Many physicists dislike the idea that something happens just because an observer is "looking," including David Bohm, John Bell, and Everett.

Barrett writes that there are many "many-worlds" models and many "many-minds" models as well. He personally supports a "single-mind Q theory" (Minds and Worlds, pp.204-206)

In the effort to guarantee that one has made an observer’s measurement records determinate, one might add a physical hidden-variable Q to the standard quantum-mechanical state such that Q is that physical quantity on which mental records in fact supervene, whatever this happens to be. The quantum-mechanical state evolves in the usual linear way, and an auxiliary dynamics describes the evolution of the determinate value of Q just as the auxiliary dynamics describes the evolution of determinate particle positions in Bohmian mechanics. The value of Q plays the role of the determinate mental states in the single-mind theory by guaranteeing determinate mental records, but here one seeks to exchange mind–body dualism for a variety of physical–physical dualism.

This Q-theory solves the quantum measurement problem if and only if there is a single physical quantity Q on which all mental records in fact supervene. Simply stipulating that there is a just-right physical quantity Q that is always determinate and in fact determines all mental states looks more than a little ad hoc. Moreover, since one is left with a hidden-variable theory where there are two very different types of physical parameters, the quantum-mechanical state and the determinate physical quantities, each with their own dynamical laws, one has arguably not altogether escaped from committing to a strong metaphysical dualism.

Works
For Teachers
For Scholars
Notes

1.

Bibliography

Chapter 1.4 - The Philosophy Chapter 1.6 - The Scientists
Home Part Two - Knowledge
Normal | Teacher | Scholar