Citation for this page in APA citation style.           Close


Philosophers

Mortimer Adler
Rogers Albritton
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Samuel Alexander
William Alston
Anaximander
G.E.M.Anscombe
Anselm
Louise Antony
Thomas Aquinas
Aristotle
David Armstrong
Harald Atmanspacher
Robert Audi
Augustine
J.L.Austin
A.J.Ayer
Alexander Bain
Mark Balaguer
Jeffrey Barrett
William Barrett
William Belsham
Henri Bergson
George Berkeley
Isaiah Berlin
Richard J. Bernstein
Bernard Berofsky
Robert Bishop
Max Black
Susanne Bobzien
Emil du Bois-Reymond
Hilary Bok
Laurence BonJour
George Boole
Émile Boutroux
Daniel Boyd
F.H.Bradley
C.D.Broad
Michael Burke
Lawrence Cahoone
C.A.Campbell
Joseph Keim Campbell
Rudolf Carnap
Carneades
Nancy Cartwright
Gregg Caruso
Ernst Cassirer
David Chalmers
Roderick Chisholm
Chrysippus
Cicero
Tom Clark
Randolph Clarke
Samuel Clarke
Anthony Collins
Antonella Corradini
Diodorus Cronus
Jonathan Dancy
Donald Davidson
Mario De Caro
Democritus
Daniel Dennett
Jacques Derrida
René Descartes
Richard Double
Fred Dretske
John Dupré
John Earman
Laura Waddell Ekstrom
Epictetus
Epicurus
Austin Farrer
Herbert Feigl
Arthur Fine
John Martin Fischer
Frederic Fitch
Owen Flanagan
Luciano Floridi
Philippa Foot
Alfred Fouilleé
Harry Frankfurt
Richard L. Franklin
Bas van Fraassen
Michael Frede
Gottlob Frege
Peter Geach
Edmund Gettier
Carl Ginet
Alvin Goldman
Gorgias
Nicholas St. John Green
H.Paul Grice
Ian Hacking
Ishtiyaque Haji
Stuart Hampshire
W.F.R.Hardie
Sam Harris
William Hasker
R.M.Hare
Georg W.F. Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Heraclitus
R.E.Hobart
Thomas Hobbes
David Hodgson
Shadsworth Hodgson
Baron d'Holbach
Ted Honderich
Pamela Huby
David Hume
Ferenc Huoranszki
Frank Jackson
William James
Lord Kames
Robert Kane
Immanuel Kant
Tomis Kapitan
Walter Kaufmann
Jaegwon Kim
William King
Hilary Kornblith
Christine Korsgaard
Saul Kripke
Thomas Kuhn
Andrea Lavazza
Christoph Lehner
Keith Lehrer
Gottfried Leibniz
Jules Lequyer
Leucippus
Michael Levin
Joseph Levine
George Henry Lewes
C.I.Lewis
David Lewis
Peter Lipton
C. Lloyd Morgan
John Locke
Michael Lockwood
Arthur O. Lovejoy
E. Jonathan Lowe
John R. Lucas
Lucretius
Alasdair MacIntyre
Ruth Barcan Marcus
Tim Maudlin
James Martineau
Nicholas Maxwell
Storrs McCall
Hugh McCann
Colin McGinn
Michael McKenna
Brian McLaughlin
John McTaggart
Paul E. Meehl
Uwe Meixner
Alfred Mele
Trenton Merricks
John Stuart Mill
Dickinson Miller
G.E.Moore
Thomas Nagel
Otto Neurath
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Norton
P.H.Nowell-Smith
Robert Nozick
William of Ockham
Timothy O'Connor
Parmenides
David F. Pears
Charles Sanders Peirce
Derk Pereboom
Steven Pinker
U.T.Place
Plato
Karl Popper
Porphyry
Huw Price
H.A.Prichard
Protagoras
Hilary Putnam
Willard van Orman Quine
Frank Ramsey
Ayn Rand
Michael Rea
Thomas Reid
Charles Renouvier
Nicholas Rescher
C.W.Rietdijk
Richard Rorty
Josiah Royce
Bertrand Russell
Paul Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Jean-Paul Sartre
Kenneth Sayre
T.M.Scanlon
Moritz Schlick
John Duns Scotus
Arthur Schopenhauer
John Searle
Wilfrid Sellars
David Shiang
Alan Sidelle
Ted Sider
Henry Sidgwick
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong
Peter Slezak
J.J.C.Smart
Saul Smilansky
Michael Smith
Baruch Spinoza
L. Susan Stebbing
Isabelle Stengers
George F. Stout
Galen Strawson
Peter Strawson
Eleonore Stump
Francisco Suárez
Richard Taylor
Kevin Timpe
Mark Twain
Peter Unger
Peter van Inwagen
Manuel Vargas
John Venn
Kadri Vihvelin
Voltaire
G.H. von Wright
David Foster Wallace
R. Jay Wallace
W.G.Ward
Ted Warfield
Roy Weatherford
C.F. von Weizsäcker
William Whewell
Alfred North Whitehead
David Widerker
David Wiggins
Bernard Williams
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Susan Wolf

Scientists

David Albert
Michael Arbib
Walter Baade
Bernard Baars
Jeffrey Bada
Leslie Ballentine
Marcello Barbieri
Gregory Bateson
Horace Barlow
John S. Bell
Mara Beller
Charles Bennett
Ludwig von Bertalanffy
Susan Blackmore
Margaret Boden
David Bohm
Niels Bohr
Ludwig Boltzmann
Emile Borel
Max Born
Satyendra Nath Bose
Walther Bothe
Jean Bricmont
Hans Briegel
Leon Brillouin
Stephen Brush
Henry Thomas Buckle
S. H. Burbury
Melvin Calvin
Donald Campbell
Sadi Carnot
Anthony Cashmore
Eric Chaisson
Gregory Chaitin
Jean-Pierre Changeux
Rudolf Clausius
Arthur Holly Compton
John Conway
Jerry Coyne
John Cramer
Francis Crick
E. P. Culverwell
Antonio Damasio
Olivier Darrigol
Charles Darwin
Richard Dawkins
Terrence Deacon
Lüder Deecke
Richard Dedekind
Louis de Broglie
Stanislas Dehaene
Max Delbrück
Abraham de Moivre
Bernard d'Espagnat
Paul Dirac
Hans Driesch
John Eccles
Arthur Stanley Eddington
Gerald Edelman
Paul Ehrenfest
Manfred Eigen
Albert Einstein
George F. R. Ellis
Hugh Everett, III
Franz Exner
Richard Feynman
R. A. Fisher
David Foster
Joseph Fourier
Philipp Frank
Steven Frautschi
Edward Fredkin
Benjamin Gal-Or
Howard Gardner
Lila Gatlin
Michael Gazzaniga
Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
GianCarlo Ghirardi
J. Willard Gibbs
James J. Gibson
Nicolas Gisin
Paul Glimcher
Thomas Gold
A. O. Gomes
Brian Goodwin
Joshua Greene
Dirk ter Haar
Jacques Hadamard
Mark Hadley
Patrick Haggard
J. B. S. Haldane
Stuart Hameroff
Augustin Hamon
Sam Harris
Ralph Hartley
Hyman Hartman
Jeff Hawkins
John-Dylan Haynes
Donald Hebb
Martin Heisenberg
Werner Heisenberg
John Herschel
Basil Hiley
Art Hobson
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Don Howard
John H. Jackson
William Stanley Jevons
Roman Jakobson
E. T. Jaynes
Pascual Jordan
Eric Kandel
Ruth E. Kastner
Stuart Kauffman
Martin J. Klein
William R. Klemm
Christof Koch
Simon Kochen
Hans Kornhuber
Stephen Kosslyn
Daniel Koshland
Ladislav Kovàč
Leopold Kronecker
Rolf Landauer
Alfred Landé
Pierre-Simon Laplace
Karl Lashley
David Layzer
Joseph LeDoux
Gerald Lettvin
Gilbert Lewis
Benjamin Libet
David Lindley
Seth Lloyd
Werner Loewenstein
Hendrik Lorentz
Josef Loschmidt
Alfred Lotka
Ernst Mach
Donald MacKay
Henry Margenau
Owen Maroney
David Marr
Humberto Maturana
James Clerk Maxwell
Ernst Mayr
John McCarthy
Warren McCulloch
N. David Mermin
George Miller
Stanley Miller
Ulrich Mohrhoff
Jacques Monod
Vernon Mountcastle
Emmy Noether
Donald Norman
Alexander Oparin
Abraham Pais
Howard Pattee
Wolfgang Pauli
Massimo Pauri
Wilder Penfield
Roger Penrose
Steven Pinker
Colin Pittendrigh
Walter Pitts
Max Planck
Susan Pockett
Henri Poincaré
Daniel Pollen
Ilya Prigogine
Hans Primas
Zenon Pylyshyn
Henry Quastler
Adolphe Quételet
Pasco Rakic
Nicolas Rashevsky
Lord Rayleigh
Frederick Reif
Jürgen Renn
Giacomo Rizzolati
A.A. Roback
Emil Roduner
Juan Roederer
Jerome Rothstein
David Ruelle
David Rumelhart
Robert Sapolsky
Tilman Sauer
Ferdinand de Saussure
Jürgen Schmidhuber
Erwin Schrödinger
Aaron Schurger
Sebastian Seung
Thomas Sebeok
Franco Selleri
Claude Shannon
Charles Sherrington
Abner Shimony
Herbert Simon
Dean Keith Simonton
Edmund Sinnott
B. F. Skinner
Lee Smolin
Ray Solomonoff
Roger Sperry
John Stachel
Henry Stapp
Tom Stonier
Antoine Suarez
Leo Szilard
Max Tegmark
Teilhard de Chardin
Libb Thims
William Thomson (Kelvin)
Richard Tolman
Giulio Tononi
Peter Tse
Alan Turing
C. S. Unnikrishnan
Francisco Varela
Vlatko Vedral
Vladimir Vernadsky
Mikhail Volkenstein
Heinz von Foerster
Richard von Mises
John von Neumann
Jakob von Uexküll
C. H. Waddington
John B. Watson
Daniel Wegner
Steven Weinberg
Paul A. Weiss
Herman Weyl
John Wheeler
Jeffrey Wicken
Wilhelm Wien
Norbert Wiener
Eugene Wigner
E. O. Wilson
Günther Witzany
Stephen Wolfram
H. Dieter Zeh
Semir Zeki
Ernst Zermelo
Wojciech Zurek
Konrad Zuse
Fritz Zwicky

Presentations

Biosemiotics
Free Will
Mental Causation
James Symposium
 

INTERVISTA. Il fisico e filosofico Robert Doyle difende, proprio attraverso la scienza,
quel libero arbitrio negato da molti studiosi

Doyle: «Mente e libertà? Nascoste nei quanti»

Placido pomeriggio sul divano. Alzarsi per andare al frigorifero e prendere una bibita o restare comodamente seduti? Non una grande decisione, eppure ci si può riflettere qualche secondo, poi scegliere e infine alzarsi.

«Il Bene oggettivo esiste: è conservare le strutture di informazione dell'uomo contro l'entropia, incarnazione del diavolo»

Niente di strano, nulla da spiegare per la maggior parte di noi. Non useremmo i termini tecnici di “libero arbitrio” e “causazione mentale”, ma ciò cui ci riferiamo è proprio l’idea che davanti a noi abbiamo corsi di azione alternativi tra cui optare senza costrizioni (restare seduti o alzarsi) e che la nostra “mente” comanda il corpo in modo diretto. Ma le cose non sono affatto così semplici. Semplificando molto, se ogni cosa ha una causa fisica (come la scienza sembra dirci) che segue le leggi immutabili della natura, non siamo liberi, ma determinati, e non ci sono cause mentali, ma solo il cervello che agisce.

«È lo scandalo della filosofia», dice Robert Doyle, astronomo e creatore di tecnologia, docente alla Harvard University, convertito con zelo militante e inesausto alla causa del libero arbitrio. Così ha intitolato anche un suo recente, denso volume (disponibile liberamente su Internet nel ricchissimo sito www.informationphilosopher.com). Come mettere fine allo scandalo costituito dal negare la libertà degli esseri umani e la realtà della mente, dovuto all’affermarsi del riduzionismo materialistico? Doyle, 76 anni, in questi giorni a Milano, ha un’idea precisa, legata alla meccanica quantistica. «La domanda centrale del classico problema mente-corpo è come una mente immateriale possa muovere un corpo materiale se le catene causali sono limitate all’interazione tra oggetti fisici», spiega. «In sintesi, il mio modello prevede una mente immateriale come pura informazione all’interno del sistema fisico che elabora quell’informazione, ovvero il cervello. In questo modo, si arriva a un fisicalismo non riduttivo e un dualismo emergentistico». Il punto sta nella maniera in cui è concepita l’informazione (che, tra l’altro, è proprio quella cosa che sta nei messaggi che ci scambiamo e nei libri che leggiamo).

«L’informazione – dice Doyle – è fisica ma immateriale. Non è né materia né energia, anche se ha bisogno di entrambe per la sua manifestazione. L’indeterminismo della fisica quantistica “rompe” la catene causali usate per ridurre i fenomeni biologici alla fisica e alla chimica e gli eventi mentali agli eventi neuronali. Ma ciò non vuole dire che le nostre scelte siano casuali». Il quadro qui si complica. Una delle difficoltà del libero arbitrio discende dal fatto che è incompatibile con il determinismo (tutto è già scritto), ma anche con l’indeterminismo (se non ci sono leggi costanti, le nostre azioni e i loro risultati saranno casuali, e libertà non è tirare ogni volta la monetina). La meccanica quantistica dice in sintesi che il comportamento delle particelle subatomiche si descrive secondo probabilità e non certezze, anche se poi le previsioni permesse dalla teoria sono accuratissime. Doyle (con altri studiosi) propone allora di spiegare come l’intuizione della nostra libertà sia supportata da un modello “a due stadi”.

«Il modello Cogito – riassume il fisico-filosofo – implica che molti eventi casuali a livello quantistico creino genuine possibilità alternative nel cervello. La mente informazionale, registratore e riproduttore di esperienze, grazie alla volontà può dare il suo assenso a una di esse, con una scelta adeguatamente determinata (cioè non casuale), facendo in modo che la possibilità di un futuro aperto si trasformi in un passato chiuso e inalterabile». Ciò ha a che fare con il collasso della funzione d’onda, uno dei concetti chiave della fisica quantistica. Una soluzione al mistero della libertà (e della causazione mentale) che non convince tutti gli studiosi, ma ha il pregio di fornire una spiegazione scientifica a un’intuizione fortissima del senso comune e di resistere al materialismo riduzionistico. Doyle trova spazio anche per una lettura morale: «Esiste un Bene oggettivo? Secondo me sì: ha la forma della conservazione delle strutture di informazione (quelle che danno vita all’uomo) contro l’entropia, che è l’incarnazione del diavolo».

IL CONVEGNO

DAL LABORATORIO ALLA METAFISICA. E RITORNO

Si apre oggi pomeriggio all'Università Cattolica (via Nirone, 15) il convegno 'La fisica quantistica incontra la filosofìa della mente ' (Programma). Chiamati a raccolta per tre giorni da Antonella Corradini e da Uwe Meixner dell'Università di Augusta, si confrontano i maggiori esperti (Kane, Stapp, Hameroff, Doyle) dell'applicazione della scienza ai dilemmi legati all'essere umano, alla sua costituzione e alla sua libertà.

Andrea Lavazza


Rough (Google) translation

Doyle: "Mind and freedom? Hidden in quanta »

A placid afternoon on the couch. Should you get up to go to the fridge and grab a drink or stay sitting comfortably? Not a big decision, but you can meditate for a few seconds, then choose and then get up. Nothing strange, nothing to explain to most of us. We would not use the technical terms of "free will" and "mental causation", but what we are referring to is precisely the idea that we have before us alternative courses of action including without any constraints the options (sit or stand up) and that our "mind" controls the body directly. But things are not so simple. In very simple terms, if everything has a physical cause (such as science seems to be saying), it follows from the immutable laws of nature that we are not free, but determined, and that there are no mental causes, but only the brain that acts.

"It is the scandal in philosophy," says Robert Doyle, astronomer and creator of technology, a professor at Harvard University, converted with zeal and tireless activist for the cause of free will. So he titled his recent, dense volume (available freely on the Internet in the rich website www.informationphilosopher.com). How to put an end to the scandal of denying the freedom of human beings and the reality of the mind, due to the emergence of materialistic reductionism? Doyle, 76, these days in Milan, has a clear idea, related to quantum mechanics. "The central question of the classic mind-body problem is how an immaterial mind can move a material body if causal chains are limited to the interaction between physical objects," he explains. 'In short, my model predicts a immaterial mind as pure information within the physical system that processes that information, or the brain. In this way, we arrive at a non-reductive physicalism and emergent dualism. " The point lies in the manner in which the information is intended (which, by the way, is the very thing that is in the messages that we exchange and in the books we read).

"The information - says Doyle - is physical but immaterial. It is neither matter nor energy, even if it needs both for its manifestation. The indeterminism of quantum physics "breaks" the causal chains used to reduce biological phenomena in physics and chemistry and mental events to neural events. But that does not mean that our choices are random. " The picture here is complicated. One of the problems stems from the fact that free will is incompatible with determinism (everything is already written), but also with indeterminism (if there are consistent laws, our actions and their results will be random, and freedom is not pulling the coin each time). Quantum mechanics says in summary that the behavior of subatomic particles is described according to probabilities and not certainties, even if the weather permitted by the theory are very accurate. Doyle (with other scholars) proposes then to explain how the intuition of our freedom model is supported by a "two-stage" model.

"The Cogito model - summarizes the physicist-philosopher - includes a lot of random events at the quantum level that create genuine alternative possibilities in the brain. The informational mind (an experience recorder and reproducer) can give its assent to to one of these, with its choice adequately determined (ie non-random), making sure that the possibility of an open future turns into a past closed and unalterable. " This has to do with the collapse of the wave function, one of the key concepts of quantum physics. A solution to the mystery of freedom (and of mental causation) that does not convince all scholars, but has the advantage of providing a scientific explanation for the strong intuition and common sense to resist the reductionist materialism.

Doyle also has space for a moral reading: "There is a good, objective? I think so: it has the form of the conservation of information structures (those that give life to man) against entropy, which is the incarnation of the devil.


My submission to Andrea Lavazza (he did not use this)

Do We Have Free Will?

Professor Antonella Corradini of Cathoic University has convened a conference at Catholic University this week with experts from all over the world asking whether quantum physics can help us to understand the power of mind over matter, the problem that René Descartes posed nearly 400 years ago in his Principles of Philosophy, and the problem of free will that Greek thinkers like Democritus and Epicurus puzzled over at the dawn of philosophy over 2000 years ago.

How can it possibly be that with all these years to think about the problem of free will and the mind-body problem, that they are still problems taught in philosophy classes around the world? Even more astonishing, why do so many modern scientists think that the problems will be solved some day by finding underlying causes that will explain our every action!

Neuroscientists, probing our brains with magnetic resonance imaging, are sure they are about to see how our neurons are in charge of our actions. Cognitive scientists, who think that our brains are simply computers, think they will soon discover the programming that shows we are all simply warm-blooded robots.

When most people of common sense think that we are deciding what to do, and are willing to take responsibility for our actions, except when we are obviously limited by powers beyond our control, whether external force or internal compulsions, how can our schools be teaching impressionable young minds that they are biological machines whose every action is completely determined?

In a recent survey, sixty percent of philosophers think that our free will is compatible with being determined, as long as we are one of the links in the causal chain determined by the laws of nature. Ten percent say there is no free will at all. Only thirteen percent think we have free will, and two-thirds of those have strong religious leanings, typically Catholics who are taught that free will is a gift of God.

This brings us back to the deep reasons for the original problems and why they are still with us. Democritus invented the idea of deterministic laws of nature around 400 B.C.E. to deny that the whims of arbitrary gods were manipulating our fates. Everything, including ourselves, is made of tiny atoms following universal laws of motion. And stop worrying about the gods, he said, they are too busy to be interfering in our lives.

About a hundred years later, his fellow atomist and materialist, Epicurus, was appalled that our actions might be completely determined. “It’s better to follow the myth about the gods than to be slaves to the ‘fate’ of the physicists,” he said. “We can pray to the gods for forgiveness, but physics gives us no freedom.” Epicurus, and his interpreter, the great Roman poet, Lucretius, pointed to the way out. A tiny “swerve” (clinamen, declinando) of the atoms in our minds, at no fixed time or place (nec tempore certo nec regione loci certa) “breaks the bonds of fate” (fati foedera rumpat) and we can go wherever our minds take us (sed ubi ipsa tulit mens).

With two thousand years of progress behind him, Descartes thought he had found a similar answer, a special freedom could be found in an “undetermined mind.” Although our minds are finite, compared to the infinite mind of God, so we cannot expect to understand it, he said, it would be absurd to deny our free will just because we cannot comprehend it. And then he proclaimed two things, “Freedom of the will is self-evident,” and “It is also certain that everything was pre-ordained by God.”

If we substitute for belief in God the scientists’ belief that they are discovering the laws of nature, you see the current dilemma.

Can quantum physics show us the way out? When Albert Einstein in 1916 finished his work on relativity, he found that quantum particles appeared spontaneously, at no particular time, going in no particular direction. Here was Epicurus “swerve” exactly. But Einstein simply could not believe it. God does not play dice,” he said.

Our most practical and plausible solution to the problem of free will is that quantum events in our brains are the origins of freely generated creative new ideas that neither laws nor gods could have pre-determined or pre-ordained. In a second step, we then evaluate these “random” ideas that “pop into our heads,” in the light of our motives, reasons, desires, and we select the best one in an “adequately determined” way. Our actions are caused, but some of the causes originate in our own minds, as Epicurus and Descartes thought. Our minds can therefore control our bodies, as Corradini’s conference participants hope to show, despite the claims of most philosophers and scientists.

According to the new “information philosophy” of Harvard philosopher and scientist Bob Doyle, our minds are simply the abstract information processing in our brains. This solves the “mind-body problem.” Information is neither matter nor energy, though it needs matter for its embodiment and energy for communication. Information is immaterial, the software in the brain hardware, the “ghost in the machine,” the modern spirit or soul.

Our immaterial minds exercise our free will in two stages, first the free generation of new thoughts, followed by the willed selection of the best action. We solve the problem of “free will” by breaking it into two parts - first “free,” then “will.”

Bob Doyle
Information Philosopher
Astronomy Department
Harvard University

For Avvenire
2 June 2013

Normal | Teacher | Scholar