Philosophers
Mortimer Adler Rogers Albritton Alexander of Aphrodisias Samuel Alexander William Alston Anaximander G.E.M.Anscombe Anselm Louise Antony Thomas Aquinas Aristotle David Armstrong Harald Atmanspacher Robert Audi Augustine J.L.Austin A.J.Ayer Alexander Bain Mark Balaguer Jeffrey Barrett William Barrett William Belsham Henri Bergson George Berkeley Isaiah Berlin Richard J. Bernstein Bernard Berofsky Robert Bishop Max Black Susanne Bobzien Emil du Bois-Reymond Hilary Bok Laurence BonJour George Boole Émile Boutroux Daniel Boyd F.H.Bradley C.D.Broad Michael Burke Jeremy Butterfield Lawrence Cahoone C.A.Campbell Joseph Keim Campbell Rudolf Carnap Carneades Nancy Cartwright Gregg Caruso Ernst Cassirer David Chalmers Roderick Chisholm Chrysippus Cicero Tom Clark Randolph Clarke Samuel Clarke Anthony Collins Antonella Corradini Diodorus Cronus Jonathan Dancy Donald Davidson Mario De Caro Democritus Daniel Dennett Jacques Derrida René Descartes Richard Double Fred Dretske John Dupré John Earman Laura Waddell Ekstrom Epictetus Epicurus Austin Farrer Herbert Feigl Arthur Fine John Martin Fischer Frederic Fitch Owen Flanagan Luciano Floridi Philippa Foot Alfred Fouilleé Harry Frankfurt Richard L. Franklin Bas van Fraassen Michael Frede Gottlob Frege Peter Geach Edmund Gettier Carl Ginet Alvin Goldman Gorgias Nicholas St. John Green H.Paul Grice Ian Hacking Ishtiyaque Haji Stuart Hampshire W.F.R.Hardie Sam Harris William Hasker R.M.Hare Georg W.F. Hegel Martin Heidegger Heraclitus R.E.Hobart Thomas Hobbes David Hodgson Shadsworth Hodgson Baron d'Holbach Ted Honderich Pamela Huby David Hume Ferenc Huoranszki Frank Jackson William James Lord Kames Robert Kane Immanuel Kant Tomis Kapitan Walter Kaufmann Jaegwon Kim William King Hilary Kornblith Christine Korsgaard Saul Kripke Thomas Kuhn Andrea Lavazza James Ladyman Christoph Lehner Keith Lehrer Gottfried Leibniz Jules Lequyer Leucippus Michael Levin Joseph Levine George Henry Lewes C.I.Lewis David Lewis Peter Lipton C. Lloyd Morgan John Locke Michael Lockwood Arthur O. Lovejoy E. Jonathan Lowe John R. Lucas Lucretius Alasdair MacIntyre Ruth Barcan Marcus Tim Maudlin James Martineau Nicholas Maxwell Storrs McCall Hugh McCann Colin McGinn Michael McKenna Brian McLaughlin John McTaggart Paul E. Meehl Uwe Meixner Alfred Mele Trenton Merricks John Stuart Mill Dickinson Miller G.E.Moore Thomas Nagel Otto Neurath Friedrich Nietzsche John Norton P.H.Nowell-Smith Robert Nozick William of Ockham Timothy O'Connor Parmenides David F. Pears Charles Sanders Peirce Derk Pereboom Steven Pinker U.T.Place Plato Karl Popper Porphyry Huw Price H.A.Prichard Protagoras Hilary Putnam Willard van Orman Quine Frank Ramsey Ayn Rand Michael Rea Thomas Reid Charles Renouvier Nicholas Rescher C.W.Rietdijk Richard Rorty Josiah Royce Bertrand Russell Paul Russell Gilbert Ryle Jean-Paul Sartre Kenneth Sayre T.M.Scanlon Moritz Schlick John Duns Scotus Arthur Schopenhauer John Searle Wilfrid Sellars David Shiang Alan Sidelle Ted Sider Henry Sidgwick Walter Sinnott-Armstrong Peter Slezak J.J.C.Smart Saul Smilansky Michael Smith Baruch Spinoza L. Susan Stebbing Isabelle Stengers George F. Stout Galen Strawson Peter Strawson Eleonore Stump Francisco Suárez Richard Taylor Kevin Timpe Mark Twain Peter Unger Peter van Inwagen Manuel Vargas John Venn Kadri Vihvelin Voltaire G.H. von Wright David Foster Wallace R. Jay Wallace W.G.Ward Ted Warfield Roy Weatherford C.F. von Weizsäcker William Whewell Alfred North Whitehead David Widerker David Wiggins Bernard Williams Timothy Williamson Ludwig Wittgenstein Susan Wolf Scientists David Albert Michael Arbib Walter Baade Bernard Baars Jeffrey Bada Leslie Ballentine Marcello Barbieri Gregory Bateson Horace Barlow John S. Bell Mara Beller Charles Bennett Ludwig von Bertalanffy Susan Blackmore Margaret Boden David Bohm Niels Bohr Ludwig Boltzmann Emile Borel Max Born Satyendra Nath Bose Walther Bothe Jean Bricmont Hans Briegel Leon Brillouin Stephen Brush Henry Thomas Buckle S. H. Burbury Melvin Calvin Donald Campbell Sadi Carnot Anthony Cashmore Eric Chaisson Gregory Chaitin Jean-Pierre Changeux Rudolf Clausius Arthur Holly Compton John Conway Simon Conway-Morris Jerry Coyne John Cramer Francis Crick E. P. Culverwell Antonio Damasio Olivier Darrigol Charles Darwin Richard Dawkins Terrence Deacon Lüder Deecke Richard Dedekind Louis de Broglie Stanislas Dehaene Max Delbrück Abraham de Moivre Bernard d'Espagnat Paul Dirac Hans Driesch John Dupré John Eccles Arthur Stanley Eddington Gerald Edelman Paul Ehrenfest Manfred Eigen Albert Einstein George F. R. Ellis Hugh Everett, III Franz Exner Richard Feynman R. A. Fisher David Foster Joseph Fourier Philipp Frank Steven Frautschi Edward Fredkin Augustin-Jean Fresnel Benjamin Gal-Or Howard Gardner Lila Gatlin Michael Gazzaniga Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen GianCarlo Ghirardi J. Willard Gibbs James J. Gibson Nicolas Gisin Paul Glimcher Thomas Gold A. O. Gomes Brian Goodwin Joshua Greene Dirk ter Haar Jacques Hadamard Mark Hadley Patrick Haggard J. B. S. Haldane Stuart Hameroff Augustin Hamon Sam Harris Ralph Hartley Hyman Hartman Jeff Hawkins John-Dylan Haynes Donald Hebb Martin Heisenberg Werner Heisenberg Grete Hermann John Herschel Basil Hiley Art Hobson Jesper Hoffmeyer Don Howard John H. Jackson William Stanley Jevons Roman Jakobson E. T. Jaynes Pascual Jordan Eric Kandel Ruth E. Kastner Stuart Kauffman Martin J. Klein William R. Klemm Christof Koch Simon Kochen Hans Kornhuber Stephen Kosslyn Daniel Koshland Ladislav Kovàč Leopold Kronecker Rolf Landauer Alfred Landé Pierre-Simon Laplace Karl Lashley David Layzer Joseph LeDoux Gerald Lettvin Gilbert Lewis Benjamin Libet David Lindley Seth Lloyd Werner Loewenstein Hendrik Lorentz Josef Loschmidt Alfred Lotka Ernst Mach Donald MacKay Henry Margenau Owen Maroney David Marr Humberto Maturana James Clerk Maxwell Ernst Mayr John McCarthy Warren McCulloch N. David Mermin George Miller Stanley Miller Ulrich Mohrhoff Jacques Monod Vernon Mountcastle Emmy Noether Donald Norman Travis Norsen Alexander Oparin Abraham Pais Howard Pattee Wolfgang Pauli Massimo Pauri Wilder Penfield Roger Penrose Steven Pinker Colin Pittendrigh Walter Pitts Max Planck Susan Pockett Henri Poincaré Daniel Pollen Ilya Prigogine Hans Primas Zenon Pylyshyn Henry Quastler Adolphe Quételet Pasco Rakic Nicolas Rashevsky Lord Rayleigh Frederick Reif Jürgen Renn Giacomo Rizzolati A.A. Roback Emil Roduner Juan Roederer Jerome Rothstein David Ruelle David Rumelhart Robert Sapolsky Tilman Sauer Ferdinand de Saussure Jürgen Schmidhuber Erwin Schrödinger Aaron Schurger Sebastian Seung Thomas Sebeok Franco Selleri Claude Shannon Charles Sherrington Abner Shimony Herbert Simon Dean Keith Simonton Edmund Sinnott B. F. Skinner Lee Smolin Ray Solomonoff Roger Sperry John Stachel Henry Stapp Tom Stonier Antoine Suarez Leo Szilard Max Tegmark Teilhard de Chardin Libb Thims William Thomson (Kelvin) Richard Tolman Giulio Tononi Peter Tse Alan Turing C. S. Unnikrishnan Nico van Kampen Francisco Varela Vlatko Vedral Vladimir Vernadsky Mikhail Volkenstein Heinz von Foerster Richard von Mises John von Neumann Jakob von Uexküll C. H. Waddington James D. Watson John B. Watson Daniel Wegner Steven Weinberg Paul A. Weiss Herman Weyl John Wheeler Jeffrey Wicken Wilhelm Wien Norbert Wiener Eugene Wigner E. O. Wilson Günther Witzany Stephen Wolfram H. Dieter Zeh Semir Zeki Ernst Zermelo Wojciech Zurek Konrad Zuse Fritz Zwicky Presentations Biosemiotics Free Will Mental Causation James Symposium |
John Dupré
John Dupré is a philosopher of science who strongly criticizes the familiar notions of causality and determinism. He is skeptical about the idea of causal closure, that every physical event has a necessary and sufficient physical cause. This leads him to reject reductionism, the popular idea that biology is reducible to chemistry, and chemistry to physics.
With determinism rejected, Dupré considers the problem of free will, but could not get beyond the standard argument against free will until his most recent work examining the right role for determinism.
In his 1993 book The Disorder of Things, an attack on the "Unity of Science" movement, he proposed a refutation of reductionism and determinism.
The best way to introduce the position against which this book will argue is to consider the continuing influence of one particularly notorious founding metaphor of modern science, the idea that the universe should be considered as a gigantic machine. Traditionally the favored machine has been a clock... Anyone who thinks that such mechanical metaphors have faded in significance might reflect on the amount of scientific effort that has been devoted in recent years to investigation of the hypothesis that the human brain — and generally also the human mind — is really a kind of calculating machine, or computer. The philosophical thesis most intimately connected with this mechanistic metaphor is determinism. The cosmic clock, we must assume given its provenance, has always told the correct time and always will. To achieve such precision its components must exhibit the same unvarying reliability as the whole. Once the clock is wound up and set in motion, its behavior and that of all its parts are determined for all eternity. ...the current vogue for chaos theory suggests that certain aspects of this complexity may be in principle beyond the reach of certain kinds of comprehension, notably prediction. Nevertheless, the metaphysical conceptions of order that originated in the picture of the mechanical universe seem to have been little threatened, if sometimes modified, by such developments. The case of chaos theory nicely illustrates this resilience. Prediction, though long conceived as a very central excellence of scientific understanding, is a goal that has tended to recede rather than approach as various scientific disciplines have increased their understanding of the complexity of the phenomena within their domains. Chaos theory appears to confront prediction not merely with an insuperable practical difficulty, but with a logically impassable obstacle. Yet paradoxically determinism, the metaphysical underlay of :he possibility of prediction, is strengthened rather than threatened by this development. For the central mathematical functions of chaos theory are quite deterministic...Even the increasing prevalence of probabilistic rather than deterministic hypotheses and methods from quantum mechanics up through the scientific hierarchy has not, I shall argue, led to the rejection of some of the most fundamental features of the deterministic world view.Dupré describes the reductionism idea that he is rejecting. To begin with, it will help to introduce what is perhaps both the clearest and the strongest version, which I shall call classical reductionism. Assume, first, a hierarchical classification of objects in which the objects at each level are complex structures of the objects com- prising the next-lower level. Paul Oppenheim and Hilary Putnam propose the following levels: elementary particles, atoms, molecules, living cells, multicellular organisms, and social groups. The investigation of each level is the task of a particular domain of science, which aims to discern the laws governing the behavior of the objects at that level. Reduction consists in deriving the laws at each higher (reduced) level from the laws governing the objects at the next-lower (reducing) level. Such reduction, in addition to knowledge of the laws at both the reducing and reduced levels, will also require so-called bridge principles (or bridge laws) identifying the kinds of objects at the reduced level with particular structures of the objects at the reducing level. Given the transitivity of such deductive derivation, the endpoint of this program will reveal the whole of science to have been derived from nothing but the laws of the lowest level and the bridge principles. The lowest level will be the physics of elementary particles. Thus, finally, truly basic science need concern itself only with the objects described by particle physics.He asks, what is wrong with this idea of reduction? The argument that must be addressed here turns on the requirement that explanations at different structural levels must at least be consistent with one another. Certain views about the nature of causality suggest that only some kind of reductive relation between higher and lower levels can achieve such consistency. Although it is not easy to find direct statements of such an argument, I believe that it underlies a good deal of continued insistence on at least the weaker versions of reductionism. It also provides a link between two of the pillars of the mechanistic picture of the world that it is the aim of this book to oppose. Although I am here considering how an assumption about causality entails reductionism, it can equally well serve as an argument from the falsity of reductionism to the falsity of the view of causality in question. The crucial assumption about causality is what I shall refer to as the assumption of causal completeness. This is the assumption that for every event there is a complete causal story to account for its occurrence. Obviously enough, this is a view of causality the roots of which are to be found in the soil of determinism. The paradigm of a complete causal story is the sufficient (and perhaps even necessary) antecedent condition provided by a deterministic causal explanation. However, since the issue of causal completeness at the microphysical level is central to the present discussion, and since microphysics is generally agreed, in the light of contemporary interpretations of quantum mechanics, to be irreducibly indeterministic, it is important to consider the indeterministic analogue of deterministic causal completeness. It is not hard to see what this should be. The basic idea is that there should be some set of antecedent conditions that together determine some precise probability of the event in question. Events and their causal explanations are conceived at particular levels of organization. The mutual annihilation of an electron and a positron is an event at the subatomic level; my thinking of the previous example is an event at the mental level; a supernova is an event at the astronomic level; and so on. However, events at lower levels may very well be constituents of events at higher levels, and it is this that leads readily from the commitment to causal completeness to an argument for some kind of reductionism. The argument is most easily seen in terms of a simple example. Consider an electron in my index finger. As I move my finger to type the letter b on my keyboard, the electron must move. Causal completeness at the level of elementary particles implies that there is some condition of events at that level sufficient to explain the movement of the electron. Suppose, then, that I offer some causal story at the macroscopic level about the movement of my hand. For example, suppose my hand moved because I intended to type the letter b, or, for those who deny that this is a causal explanation, suppose that my finger was dragged down by my typing instructor.
A Note on Freedom of the Will
Although the problem of freedom of the will is generally understood as involving a conflict between human freedom and determinism, the rejection of determinism has not generally been perceived as providing a solution to the problem of human freedom. There are good reasons for caution here. It has occasionally been suggested that quantum mechanics, by showing that certain events can occur without determining antecedent conditions, shows how human actions could be free. Perhaps a movement is somehow generated by an amplified quantum event. But a solution to the problem of freedom of the will is not to be obtained by replacing the picture of a person as mindless machinery with that of a random action generator. The idea that people act for reasons seems more reconcilable with an account under which those reasons turn out to be nothing but states of the machine, than one which seems to preclude either causes or reasons by placing the action wholly beyond explanation. Nor is it helpful to move from determinism to a probabilistic uniformitarianism that claims that human actions are not determined by antecedent physical conditions, but only made more or less probable. This sounds not so much like an account of a (metaphysically) free person, as of a somewhat unreliable one. But the effect on our conception of human freedom of relaxing the assumption of determinism can be seen quite differently. One of the problems with the quantum amplifier account of freedom is that, just as with human freedom under traditional libertarian accounts, the quantum indeterminacy is treated as a source of anomaly in a world otherwise driven by inexorable laws. A more radical rejection of complete and pervasive causal order suggests a quite different but much more promising approach. To the philosophically uncorrupted, what is striking about humans as compared with other natural phenomena is not their unpredictability or their role as sources of disorder in an otherwise reliable and well-ordered universe. Quite the contrary: it is people who appear as somewhat orderly and predictable entities in a generally chaotic world. Where we find order, it is generally because it has been intentionally created by other humans...The point is just that humans have all kinds of causal capacities that nothing else in our world has: capacities most notably to make and execute all manner of plans capable of determining their behavior in complexly organized ways for considerable distances into the future. There is no good reason for projecting these uniquely human capacities in a reductionist style onto inanimate bits of matter. Nor is there anything ultimately mysterious about particular causal capacities' being exhibited uniquely by certain very complex entities; no more than it is insolubly mysterious that certain weather patterns can generate tornadoes capable of picking up houses or that leguminous plants have the capacity to fix nitrogen. Thus the solution I propose to the free will problem is simply to recognize that what is problematic about humans is not that they are exceptions to an otherwise seamless web of causal connection, but that they are extraordinarily dense concentrations of causal capacity in a world in which such order is in short supply. Scientific investigation of the sources of these capacities may help to explain how this is possible; but this is to begin to explain, not, as determinists often want to suggest, increasingly to problematize, this remarkable feature of humans. It is natural, on the view I am presenting, to feel considerable sympathy for one aspect of Kant's account of freedom in terms of autonomy (1785/1948). It is the ability to do what one thinks one ought to do rather than what, at that moment, one would like to do that is, arguably, uniquely human, and that makes possible the execution of long complex schemes. Unlike Kant, I do not mean to restrict what one ought to do to a narrow sense of duty (although conceivably this may serve to distinguish a qualitatively distinct and higher form of conduct), but to include any prudential "ought" driven by any kind of human project. Thus planning an armed robbery or a racist political advertisement is, in the sense I am considering, as much a display of uniquely human capacities as building a hospital or dismantling a nuclear weapons system. The most relevant differentiation from Kant's position that I want to insist on is that without the commitment to determinism or even causal completeness, I am under no pressure to engage in the kind of metaphysical excesses in the noumenal world that have made Kant's position so implausible. Works
The Solution to the Problem of the Freedom of the Will, Philosophical Perspectives 10, 385-402 (1995) |